Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-wzw2p Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-02T02:03:20.108Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Science, Technology, and Utopia

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 April 2024

Emily Klancher Merchant*
Affiliation:
Department of Science and Technology Studies, University of California, Davis, CA, USA
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Symposium
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of Social Science History Association

Slouching Towards Utopia presents a whirlwind history of the political economy of the world during what J. Bradford DeLong calls the “long twentieth century” from 1870 to 2010. Yet it suffers from three problems that could be addressed through a deeper engagement with science and technology studies: technological determinism, economic absolutism, and economic realism.

Technological determinism is the description of technological change as inevitable and proceeding according to its own logic. In Slouching Towards Utopia, DeLong presents technology as the primary driver of economic growth but never explores how technology itself changes. He explains that

my estimate – or my very crude personal guess – of the average worldwide pace of what is at the core of humanity’s economic growth, the proportional rate of growth of my index of the value of the stock of useful ideas about manipulating nature and organizing humans that were discovered, developed, and deployed into the world economy, shot up from about 0.45 percent per year before 1870 to 2.1 percent per year afterward, truly a watershed boundary-crossing difference (3).

This is an impressive increase in a totally made-up metric of a vague notion of “science and technology.” It suggests that science and technology advances teleologically, grows cumulatively, and straightforwardly improves the human condition. In this view, technological development is exogenous to society, accreting in the background as the primary driver of the economic growth that is DeLong’s focus. What is missing are the historical circumstances that may have caused an investment in productive technology to increase right around 1870, such as the abolition of slavery in the United States (Levy Reference Levy2021).

DeLong is absolutely correct that technology has been a defining feature of the twentieth century, but its historical role has been much more complicated than he suggests. As an example, DeLong presents the development of labor-saving household technology in the mid-twentieth century as just that: something that reduced the amount of work women had to do in the home so that “a great deal of female labor that had previously been tied to full-time work within the household could now be redirected to other purposes” (328). There is no sense of the complexities of these or other technologies, or of the ways in which they created, as Ruth Schwartz Cowan (Reference Cowan1983) put it 40 years ago, “more work for mother” because the gendered division of labor is a social phenomenon, not one determined by the availability of technology. Later in the book, DeLong presents the development of containerized shipping and information technology as two innovations that increased the pace of global economic growth in the final decades of the twentieth century. They certainly had this effect, but, in DeLong’s account, these and other technologies seem to simply arise organically and have straightforwardly positive consequences. DeLong explains that more attention to “precisely how new technologies have advanced human collective powers over nature” (469) would have required a different book, one written by an engineer, but that kind of information isn’t necessary. What would improve DeLong’s history is the recognition that new technologies don’t simply advance “human collective powers over nature” (469). They also advance the powers of some humans over other humans, and most technologies have been specifically designed to do exactly that (e.g., Edwards Reference Edwards1997; Levinson Reference Levinson2016).

Economic absolutism is the presentation of economic metrics as if their meanings were transhistorical and absolute. One example in Slouching Towards Utopia is the measure of humanity’s overall wealth. DeLong explains that global wealth is now more than eight times what it was in 1870, interpreting this metric as a measure of humanity’s overall well-being. Wealth represents power that can be exchanged for goods and services, but humanity as a whole has nobody to exchange with. For that reason, a measure of humanity’s wealth is not analogous to a measure of the wealth of an individual or group. What it really represents is the sum total of market exchange, and as DeLong effectively shows in the book, markets can’t meet all of humanity’s needs.

To be sure, for the most people in the world, the human condition is better now than it was 150 years ago. However, global wealth is not an appropriate metric for it because it doesn’t account for inequality. It is undeniable that the US economy, as we measure it now, grew tremendously between 1870 and 1914. But to use this as a metric of American well-being, as DeLong does, would be to suggest that this prosperity was shared equitably. DeLong describes a world-historical shift occurring right around 1870. Prior to that, in his narrative, anyone who escaped grinding poverty did so through extraction and exploitation, holding everyone else down. Beginning around 1870, however, DeLong argues that globalization, modern corporations, and the industrial research lab produced enough economic growth that everyone could prosper, even as the population grew. What is missing from this account is the fact that many of the technologies that generated this growth were technologies of extraction and exploitation. For the world’s industrial nations, this was the era of imperialism abroad and robber barons at home. In the United States (the primary focus of DeLong’s book), railroad magnates enclosed public lands and stole public funds (White Reference White2011), and fossil fuel executives literally had their workers slaughtered to keep labor costs down (Gitelman Reference Gitelman1988). Any sharing of prosperity that occurred did so through organized labor, which was also facilitated by some of the same technologies (Mitchell Reference Mitchell2011). All of this is missing from Slouching Towards Utopia.

The second example of economic absolutism is DeLong’s metric of poverty. He explains that, until 1870, most people in the world were desperately poor, which DeLong defines as living on less than $2 per day in inflation-adjusted terms, or as lacking access to technologies that most of us take for granted today. There is no question that many fewer people today live on less than $2 a day in constant terms or that nobody had computers 100 years ago. But these are not historically adequate definitions of poverty. Lacking access to a technology that doesn’t exist doesn’t make you poor, nor does lacking access to cash in a world where there are other ways to meet your existential needs. Adjusting for inflation doesn’t change the fact that $2 in a world where all of your needs must be met on the market is very different than $2 in a world where there are other ways to get by. It isn’t a lack of cash that makes people poor, it is the enclosure of public goods as private property (Sen Reference Sen1987). This is an important point made by Karl Polanyi (Reference Polanyi1944) – a major theoretical touchstone in Slouching Towards Utopia – that DeLong overlooks. He describes Polanyi’s stance as being that “the market was made for man, not man for the market” (13). But Polanyi argued that markets are made by men, and it is the enclosure by markets of the means of meeting humanity’s existential needs that makes people poor.

Economic realism is the presentation of markets and economies as natural objects with a transhistorical existence rather than as social constructs. Describing markets and economies as social constructs isn’t to say they aren’t real. Rather, it is to say that they exist only because they were produced through statistical and political activities that were done by particular people in particular times and places that can be and have been documented historically. DeLong argues that the long twentieth century needs to be understood through an economic lens, and he is not wrong. But the reason it needs to be understood through an economic lens is that the twentieth century saw the statistical and political creation of a thing called “the economy” and the rise of the expectation that governments should maximize economies (Hirschman Reference Hirschman2016; Mitchell Reference Mitchell2011, Reference Mitchell2014). This history is totally missing from Slouching Towards Utopia. Also missing is the discipline of economics as a historical actor (e.g., Fourcade Reference Fourcade2006; Mitchell Reference Mitchell2005). DeLong presents the economic thought of people like Friedrich von Hayek and Milton and Rose Friedman, but he doesn’t explain just how powerful their ideas were, or the material consequences of their uptake by people who had the power to implement them (e.g., Burgin Reference Burgin2015). Instead, DeLong presents what he calls “the neoliberal turn” as a popular backlash against the previous 30 years of social democracy, as if policy in the United States were a straightforward reflection of public opinion.

References

Burgin, Angus (2015) The Great Persuasion: Reinventing Free Markets since the Depression. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Cowan, Ruth Schwartz (1983) More Work for Mother: The Ironies of Household Technology from the Open Hearth to the Microwave. New York, NY: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Edwards, Paul (1997) The Closed World: Computers and the Politics of Discourse in Cold War America. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fourcade, Marion (2006) “The construction of a global profession: The transnationalization of economics.” American Journal of Sociology 112 (1): 145–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gitelman, H. M. (1988) The Legacy of the Ludlow Massacre: A Chapter in American Industrial Relations. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hirschman, Dan (2016) “Inventing the economy (Or, how we learned to stop worrying and love the GDP).” Ph.D. diss., University of Michigan.Google Scholar
Levinson, Marc (2016) The Box: How the Shipping Container Made the World Smaller and the World Economy Bigger, 2nd ed. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Levy, Jonathan (2021) Ages of American Capitalism: A History of the United States. New York: Penguin Random House.Google Scholar
Mitchell, Timothy (2005) “The work of economics: How a discipline makes its world.” European Journal of Sociology/Archives Européennes De Sociologie 46 (2): 297320.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mitchell, Timothy (2011) Carbon Democracy: Political Power in the Age of Oil. London: Verso.Google Scholar
Mitchell, Timothy (2014) “Economentality: How the future entered government.” Critical Inquiry 40 (4): 479507.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Polanyi, Karl (1944) The Great Transformation. New York: Farrar and Rinehart.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya (1987) The Standard of Living. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
White, Richard (2011) Railroaded: The Transcontinentals and the Making of Modern America. New York: W. W. Norton.Google Scholar