Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-ndmmz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-02T07:28:01.385Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Language and doctrine in Parmenides’ Way of Reality

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 September 2023

Shaul Tor*
Affiliation:
King’s College London
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

As early as Plato and as recently as current scholarship, readers of Parmenides have diagnosed tensions of one sort or another between his ontological views and the language through which he expresses those views. In the first instance, this article examines earlier claims for such tensions and argues that they are predicated on problematic assumptions concerning Parmenides’ ontological commitments or his strictures regarding the use of language. In the second instance, however, it argues that Parmenides’ Way of Reality does indeed confront us with tensions between language and doctrine, that these tensions are more pointed and sustained than scholars generally recognize and that they can be identified independently of specific or determinate elaboration of Parmenides’ precise ontological views. This analysis discloses a reflective preoccupation with, and a consistent attitude towards, the scope and limitations of human language. Parmenides persistently evinces his awareness that his description of what-is proceeds through expressive measures that are imported with difficulty from a different domain and, consequently, are limited, indirect and often figurative. The article closes by pointing to a meaningful (but partial) affinity between Parmenides and those Platonists who placed their own ultimate philosophical and ontological principle beyond the expressive reach of words.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the Society for the Promotion of Hellenic Studies

I. Introduction

As early as Plato, readers of Parmenides have detected tensions of one sort or another between the ontological views they take him to advance and the language and imagery through which he presents those views.Footnote 1 Attention has also been given to Parmenides’ conception of ‘naming’ (ὀνομάζϵιν) and overt critiques of human naming, sometimes in connection with his few, deeply obscure remarks on speaking (and thinking) in the Way of Reality.Footnote 2 And yet, while the more unmistakable examples of tension between doctrine and language are occasionally marked in passing, scholars seldom ask what consequences such tensions should have for our understanding of Parmenides and the status of the language that makes up his poem.Footnote 3 This article takes a fresh look at this question. If there is a tension between language and ontology in Parmenides, and I will defend the view that there is, then what precisely is the nature of this tension? What should we, as interpreters of Parmenides, conclude from it?

An important step will be to disentangle clearly different sorts of potential tensions between language and doctrine. In section II, I argue that some oft purported cases of tension are best seen as specious, and that lack of clarity on this point muddies the interpretive waters. Put differently, readers and critics are sometimes too quick to declare a mismatch between Parmenides’ language and (as they see it) his doctrine. As we will see, our precise view on which aspects of the poem do or do not occasion these tensions will affect dramatically our evaluation of their interpretive significance. Existing treatments of this issue are often predicated on specific and narrow assumptions about Parmenides’ ontology, viz. that only what-is exists while all else is dismissed as non-existent illusion. But, if this used to be the standard or default interpretation of Reality, this is no longer the case and, indeed, a growing majority of scholars rejects this interpretation as unsatisfactory, or even a non-starter.Footnote 4 In the wake of this disruption of the old orthodoxy concerning Parmenides’ ontology, and the current, almost chaotic proliferation of alternative interpretive models, there is a new need to ask what can be gleaned by revisiting the tension between language and doctrine in Parmenides’ poem with fresh eyes, not beholden to the old and highly restrictive way of construing his ontological commitments, nor yet to some other, very specific or determinate ontological model.

In section III, I turn to what I consider genuine and under-discussed tensions between language and doctrine in Parmenides’ account of what-is in DK28 B8, and I suggest that these are more pointed and persistent than scholars generally recognize. My claim will not be that the expressive limitations of human language were Parmenides’ primary philosophical concern, or even that he developed a detailed, worked-out theory on this matter that he elected to convey no more overtly than the evidence we will consider. What this evidence will disclose, however, is a sustained and reflective preoccupation on Parmenides’ part with the scope, orientation and limitations of human language, as well as a consistent and critically aware attitude in response to this preoccupation. The tensions we will examine ultimately tell us something about what we can and cannot expect our words to achieve. Parmenides takes himself to be arguing conclusively for a certain view about the nature of Being, and yet it is a conception of Being that we remain unable to express through language in a full or straightforward way. The goddess puts us in a position to think and cognize (νοϵῖν) what-is. And yet, when we attempt to go beyond the secure statement that what-is is and put its characteristics into words, we quickly find ourselves straining against the expressive boundaries of our language.

On the view I defend below, the tensions between language and doctrine do not infect the logic of the goddess’ arguments. They do not undermine her inferential moves themselves. Consequently, it is not the case that, despite the various programmatic remarks indicating otherwise, Parmenides in fact places a question mark over Reality as much as he does over Opinion.Footnote 5 The difficulty posed ultimately concerns, not the acceptability of the goddess’ claims about the nature of what-is, but the expressibility of what-is itself.Footnote 6 I will also contend (in section IV) that it is textually untenable simply to deny that the goddess offers a description of what-is, even though the text does indeed confront us with challenging questions concerning the status of the language of which this description consists.Footnote 7

Some readers may find themselves uneasy about allowing daylight between, on the one hand, the intelligibility and acceptability of a philosophical principle or stance and, on the other, its expressibility in language. But, deep-seated and even well-placed as such unease may be, it must not blind us to productive interpretive possibilities in relation to the significance of the marked and striking tensions between language and ontology in Parmenides’ poem. There is a similarly entrenched and perhaps not unrelated unease among commentators to permit meaningful philosophical affinities between Parmenides and the later Platonic tradition over which he has clearly exercised (via Plato himself) significant influence. Indeed, it is no exaggeration to say that it is generally considered an interpretive desideratum to distance Parmenides from the Platonists.Footnote 8 Going against this tendency, I will unapologetically point in my conclusion to a meaningful (though partial) affinity between the Parmenides who emerges below and Plotinus, who places the ultimate philosophical and ontological principle (for him, ‘the One’) beyond the expressive reach of words.

A final point of clarification. In speaking of tensions between language and doctrine in Parmenides I will not be suggesting that we can somehow isolate the philosophical content of Parmenides’ poem from its (poetic) verbal expression and reformulate for him this content in language free of those difficulties.Footnote 9 Rather, my suggestion will be that one aspect of the poem’s philosophical content itself is a marked tension or dissonance between Parmenides’ ontological doctrine and the language through which he in fact expresses this doctrine.Footnote 10

II. Questioning some claims of tension

At one juncture in Plato’s Sophist (244b6–d13), the Eleatic Stranger argues that the monists, ‘those who say that the all is one’ (τῶν ἓν τὸ πᾶν λϵγόντων, 244b6), could not coherently express their position, let alone defend it in a dialectical exchange.Footnote 11 Although Parmenides is not mentioned here by name, Plato earlier (242c4–6, d4–6) and elsewhere (ἓν … τὸ πᾶν, Prm. 128a8–b1) presents his position in these terms.Footnote 12 The Stranger argues that the monist could not maintain that ‘being’ and ‘one’ refer to the same thing, because this would entail admitting at least two names (δύο ὀνόματα) and, therefore, at least two things (244c8–9). Indeed, even a single name would entail distinguishing between signifier (ὄνομα) and referent (πρᾶγμα) and so, again, admitting in our ontology at least two things (244d3–4). Plato cleverly underscores the difficulty through his use of ἀπόκρισις and its cognate verb.Footnote 13 If we are to give answers, or in general to speak, then we are to impose distinctions, for example between different names, or between signifiers and their referents. Really, the monist was doomed as soon as the Stranger said, ‘let them answer’ or, literally, ‘let them set things apart’ (ἀποκρινέσθων, 244b9, c4–6).Footnote 14

The Stranger’s argument targets a strict monism. Since the monist only admits the one Being, there is no logical space in their world for two names, or for both a name and a referent.Footnote 15 A similar strict conception of Reality appears to underpin the arguments of Rose Cherubin for the view that the goddess’ language betrays a problematic reliance on concepts and presuppositions imported from the opinions of mortals.Footnote 16 To take a representative example, Cherubin maintains that, by charting our progress through the steps of an argument, Parmenides helps himself to the idea of motion and change, a facet of mortal opinions that Reality had ostensibly discarded.Footnote 17 If, however, Reality never alleged that the unchanging and motionless what-is excludes the existence of everything else, then there is no obvious problem with the idea that something else (for example, humans or the goddess) can move through the premises of an argument.Footnote 18

While, thanks in no small measure to Plato’s influence, the strict interpretation of Parmenides’ ontology was once the standard or default one, this is no longer the case. The question of how what-is might relate to the heterogeneous items that permeate our everyday experiences (as well as Parmenides’ Opinion) is more contested than ever. The literature abounds with different permissive ontological models, which allow for the existence of things other than what-is. For example, on one interpretation (of which we find ancient versions in Plutarch and Simplicius), what-is is the only ‘real’ or ‘genuine’ (the key terms here are ἀληθϵίη and ἀληθής) thing, but not thereby the only thing that exists, where this means that it has a mode of being that in no way involves it with not-being and that exemplifies being perfectly. Thus, for example, there are no times or places in which it is not, and its properties (changelessness, homogeneity, indivisibility, etc.) are all held absolutely and do not implicate it in ‘more’ or ‘less’. Since it is only this eternal, unchanging and uninterrupted entity that perfectly exemplifies being, it is this that is properly thought of as that to which the term ‘Being’ (τὸ ἐόν) refers. By contrast, things like humans or trees, which are (here) but also are not (there) or are (now) but also are not (tomorrow), display throughout change, heterogeneity, external divisions and internal articulation. For Parmenides, on this view, such things thus fall short of the rubric of ‘reality’ (ἀληθϵίη) and cannot count as a (or the) ‘Being’ (τὸ ἐόν), but they are not, however, thereby dismissed as non-existent illusions.Footnote 19

To be sure, this and other permissive interpretations of Reality’s ontology all involve some difficulties, and an adequate defence of any particular ontological model will be neither possible nor necessary here. The significant point for us to underline is the negative one. Far from being obvious or the default reading, the strict interpretation that denies existence to anything but what-is, and underpins critiques like those of the Stranger and Cherubin, faces intractable difficulties. After all, if only what-is exists, then it is impossible to see how it could even appear as though other things (such as trees or humans) exist or act. The traditional dismissal of such things among strict interpreters as ‘illusions’ (a term with no counterpart in the poem) is a non-starter.Footnote 20 It would be absurd to suggest that it is the unchanging what-is that generates, experiences and is confused by those illusions, but, for strict interpreters, nothing else is there to do so. The strict interpretation asks us to imagine a Parmenides who avowedly excluded the existence of all but what-is while failing to recognize the rudimentary point that he was thereby excluding the possibility of even the appearance of things like humans and human error, or of his own poem, or indeed of a multiplicity of names.Footnote 21

One might, however, still think that Parmenides did indeed present in Reality an ontology that excluded the existence of all but what-is, that he was perfectly aware that this ontology conflicted with the language expressing it and with the appearance of the items and processes of everyday experiences, and that his purpose was precisely to leave his readers with this unresolved puzzle. It is just this paradoxical and aporetic Parmenides who emerges from the discussion in Cherubin.Footnote 22 As an interpretation of the poem’s design and dialectical stance, however, this view is also difficult to accept. The goddess’ promise to the kouros (and, by extension, the text’s promise to its reader) that he will learn ‘all things’ (B1.28) gives an air of dogmatic finality. More importantly, the asymmetrical framing of the two parts always presents Reality in thoroughly positive terms. Thus, for example, in the transition from Reality to Opinion Parmenides styles the former, by contrast with the latter, ‘a trustworthy account’ (πιστὸν λόγον, B8.50). If Parmenides in fact means to place a question mark over Reality no less than Opinion and to leave us uncertain of both, then this and other such programmatic remarks would amount to nothing short of misdirection, and it is difficult to see what the point of such misdirection would be.Footnote 23

In sum, we need not follow those who identify a tension between language and doctrine in Reality on the assumption that Parmenides expressed there strict numerical monism (whether committing himself to it or as part of an unresolved aporia). Other commentators, however, do not presume this view of Reality yet still advance a version of the Stranger’s core contention, that language’s reliance on distinctions renders it incapable of coherently articulating the Parmenidean Being. The thought here goes: if Being is unified and undivided, and if language refers and generates sense by means of imposing distinctions, then language cannot articulate Being. This is the attitude underpinning the discussions of Richard Mason and Chiara Robbiano.Footnote 24 First, however, I cannot see that our text warrants following Mason and Robbiano in ascribing this very particular view about linguistic reference and meaning to Parmenides. Second, whether we consider this line of thought an interpretation of Parmenides or an objection to him, it lacks bite. It is not clear why language’s reliance on distinctions should itself disqualify it from successfully referring to and describing something devoid of real internal divisions. The worry may be that, if our account distinguishes between Being and its predicates (‘ungenerated’, ‘homogeneous’, etc.), then it imposes on Being internal divisions that are incompatible with its undivided nature.Footnote 25 But one could fairly respond that the distinctions between Being and its predicates are conceptual rather than real. The predication that Being ‘is imperishable’ (ἀνώλϵθρόν ἐστιν, B8.3), for example, need not imply that Being and its property of imperishability are discrete items. We may compare a description of Socrates as so many feet tall, which would not imply that Socrates and his height are discrete items, and contrast a description of Socrates as wearing a green shirt, which could fairly be taken to posit Socrates and his shirt as discrete items. Parmenides throughout describes Being only in terms that involve no more than conceptual distinctions of the former sort. Being is one with its characteristic of imperishability. It is true that the account’s language itself exhibits real distinctions between discrete components (such as a subject, a copula and a predicate), but this need not preclude it from successfully describing and referring to an entity that exhibits no real distinctions between discrete components. After all, linguistic signifiers that refer successfully to, say, red or square referents need not themselves be red or square.Footnote 26

Cherubin sees a different problem with the fact that Reality’s arguments are formulated through distinctions and the principle of non-contradiction. She maintains that talk of distinctions and contradictions itself relies on mortal opinions: ‘whatever is not Light is Night, and vice versa. Together, Light and Night support distinction [and] division’.Footnote 27 In this case the poem affords a ready response. It is true that, within Opinion’s cosmology, Light and Night function as contrary or even contradictory predicates (B9). It does not follow, however, that any distinction or appeal to the principle of non-contradiction implicitly relies on those two cosmological opposites. Indeed, through his careful use of the vocabulary of krisis, Parmenides takes pains to emphasize that the principle of discrimination that frames Reality’s argumentation, between ‘[it] is’ and ‘[it] is not’, is qualitatively different from that framing Opinion’s cosmology, between ‘Light’ and ‘Night’. The latter presents us with two opposite principles, each of which is described by contrast with the other (B8.55–59) and both of which are retained in the cosmology.Footnote 28 Conversely, the goddess exhorts us to retain only one side of Reality’s discrimination: to align our notion of Being strictly with ‘[it] is’ and reject as a non-starter the idea of postulating what-is-not.Footnote 29

To close this section, let us consider two final claims on the basis of which readers have diagnosed a tension between language and doctrine in Reality: first, that Parmenides forbids speaking of what-is-not, yet does so himself; second, that Parmenides considers what-is the sole object of meaningful speech, yet continues to speak of other things as well.

It has long been held that Parmenides contravenes his own strictures about the use of language by speaking of what-is-not.Footnote 30 The two types of pertinent cases are Parmenides’ use of negative predications, as in his remark that what-is is not divisible (οὐδὲ διαιρϵτόν ἐστιν, B8.22), and his own uses of the term ‘what-is-not’. In neither case, in my view, does Parmenides contravene his strictures.Footnote 31 We must begin by clarifying just what these do and do not prohibit. In B2, the goddess states that the second road is not at all amenable to inquiry (παναπϵυθέα), explaining that one cannot know what-is-not (οὔτϵ γὰρ ἂν γνοίης τό γϵ μὴ ἐόν) nor ‘indicate’ it (οὔτϵ ϕράσαις, B2.6–8). The verb ϕράζϵιν fundamentally carries the sense ‘indicate’, ‘show’, ‘make evident’, rather than ‘say’ or ‘tell’. One might of course ‘exhibit’ or ‘explain’ something verbal (such as a μῦθος) or indicate something through the medium of speech or writing, but ϕράζϵιν can just as naturally be used when something is ‘indicated’ or ‘shown’ precisely without being spoken.Footnote 32 The goddess, then, does not prohibit all use of the expression τὸ μὴ ἐόν. Rather, she suggests that it would be a non-starter to attempt an inquiry into what-is-not or strive to grasp it or exhibit it through an account. The remark ‘it could not be accomplished’ (οὐ γὰρ ἀνυστόν, B2.7) colours putative attempts to do so as a fool’s errand: a venture that could not be completed or consummated.Footnote 33

Still, some have interpreted this claim, that we could not indicate what-is-not, as the denial that we could make coherent use of negative predications,Footnote 34 or informative and heuristically effective use of them when inquiring into the real nature of things. Footnote 35 It is difficult to accept, however, that the goddess pronounces such a stricture about inquiry (παναπϵυθέα) and knowledge or understanding (οὔτϵ γὰρ ἂν γνοίης), while she herself inquires into the nature of what-is precisely by working out systematically what it is not like and urging us to apply our mind to what is not generated, perishable, divisible, changing, etc.Footnote 36 Her third and final stricture (οὔτϵ ϕράσαις) could not suddenly be deploying ‘what-is-not’ in a different way. By ‘what-is-not’, then, the goddess does not have in mind, as is often assumed, negative predication (‘x is not F’).Footnote 37 Her concern seems to be rather with what is not anything at all, that is, what has no properties whatsoever.Footnote 38 And indeed we could not begin to inquire into, grasp or indicate what is not anything at all, and one would therefore be searching vainly for this on the forbidden road ‘that/how [it] is not and that/how [it] must not be’. This also explains why the goddess can interchangeably use ‘nothing’ (μηδέν, B6.2) as a functionally equivalent term.Footnote 39 Her point in B2.6–8, then, is that what-is-not lacks any nature, any properties whatsoever, onto which inquiry, cognition or an account could latch.Footnote 40 She reiterates this same point when she affirms that the road of inquiry into what-is-not must perforce be left ‘unconceived, unnamed’ (ἀνόητον ἀνώνυμον, B8.17).

What of the goddess’ stipulation, ‘not from what-is-not will I allow you to say or to think, for it must not be said or thought that [it] is not’ (οὔτ’ ἐκ μὴ ἐόντος ἐάσσω | ϕάσθαι σ᾽ οὐδὲ νοϵῖν· οὐ γὰρ ϕατὸν οὐδὲ νοητόν | ἔστιν ὅπως οὐκ ἔστι, B8.7–9)? This remark must be read in the context of what immediately precedes, where the goddess asks from what we might maintain that what-is emerged into being (πῇ πόθϵν, B8.6–7).Footnote 41 What the goddess prohibits here is not using the expression ‘what-is-not’, but denying the existence of what-is, asserting the existence of what-is-not or, consequently, entertaining what-is-not as a cosmological origin for what-is.

Parmenides nowhere denies our evident ability to use grammatical negations in relation to items that do have positive properties. He also nowhere pronounces the term ‘what-is-not’ unspeakable or prohibits making use of it. To begin with, then, we need not saddle Parmenides with an aversion to negative language. In the case of the term ‘what-is-not’, though, we should acknowledge that he is indeed walking a conceptual tightrope. If pressed to give an account of this term, he would have to respond that no such account could be given. But this is just the point. Parmenides asks us to choose between a viable notion that can be developed and grasped (what-is) and a conceptual non-starter (what-is-not). Suppose we were asked to choose between positing a non-round square and, alternatively, a round square in the Euclidean plane.Footnote 42 That in both instances the latter concept (‘what-is-not’, ‘round square’) is incoherent and must remain counterfactual is precisely the point. Parmenides leverages the incoherent prospect of an item without properties in order to recommend as compelling the alternative and to work out the nature of this alternative. A good example is the goddess’ use of the counterfactual prospect of what-is-not when arguing that what-is is indivisible and evenly distributed: ‘for neither is it the case that there is not-being (οὔτϵ γὰρ οὐκ ἐὸν ἔστι), which would halt it [sc. what-is] from coming into the same’ (B8.46–47). This and such uses of the term ‘what-is-not’ are not themselves incoherent nor do they contravene the goddess’ stricture that we cannot ‘indicate’ or ‘display’ what-is-not.Footnote 43

Let us turn now to the contention that the unchanging and homogeneous what-is exhausts the set of things that can be spoken of meaningfully, a view that some still-influential studies presented as key to Parmenides’ thinking.Footnote 44 Our evidence does not support this view. Whatever we think about the status of Opinion’s cosmology, there should be no question that the goddess’ account of it is not meaningless.Footnote 45 Indeed, the goddess urges the subject matter of Doxa as objects of inquiry (πυθέσθαι, B1.28; πϵύσῃ, B10.4), by contrast with what-is-not, which resists inquiry altogether (παναπϵυθέα, B2.6). The goddess’ description of wayward mortals as plying ‘an aimless eye and echoing ear and tongue’ (ἄσκοπον ὄμμα καὶ ἠχήϵσσαν ἀκουήν | καὶ γλῶσσαν, B7.4–5) plausibly refers to the attitudes that underpin the mortal world view, with ‘tongue’ in particular gesturing towards a language structured by categories such as ‘coming-into-being’, ‘perishing’ and ‘changing place’ (cf. B8.38–41).Footnote 46 It would be a stretch, however, to pin on this reference to ‘tongue’ the view that all language that describes items other than the unchanging and homogeneous what-is (including, say, the rather specific contention that the moon gets its light from the sun: B14–15) amounts to nothing more than nonsense.

We also find no tenable support for this view in the goddess’ deeply obscure remark: χρὴ τὸ λέγϵιν τὸ νοϵῖν τ’ ἐὸν ἔμμϵναι· ἔστι γὰρ ϵἶναι, | μηδὲν δ’ οὐκ ἔστιν (B6.1–2). To be sure, the syntax is (by design?) underdetermined and amenable to different syntactical construals, including (1) ‘it is necessary to say and to think that Being is; for it is to be, but nothing [it?] is not’,Footnote 47 (2) ‘it is necessary to say that this is Being and to think that this is Being, etc.’, (3) ‘it is necessary that saying and thinking be real-and-true, etc.’.Footnote 48 Far less plausible, however, is the once-popular rendering ‘what can be spoken and thought must be’.Footnote 49 This construal requires us to take τὸ … ἐὸν as a potential articular participle (‘that which it is possible …’) with the infinitives (λέγϵιν … νοϵῖν τ’) embedded in between, an extremely contorted construction for which it is difficult to find passable parallels. Charles Kahn’s harsh verdict is warranted: ‘no one would construe the verse this way except under pressure from a previously established view of what Parmenides should be saying’.Footnote 50 Quite possibly, then, B6.1 recommends to us the truth that what-is is (ἐὸν ἔμμϵναι) as a privileged object of both speech and thought; that is, as something (the one thing?) we ought to say and think without reservation (about our mode of expression or anything else).Footnote 51 This is the other side of the injunction not to say or to think that what-is-not is (B8.8–9, 17). Parmenides, however, nowhere expresses the view that what-is is the sole object of meaningful speech (let alone that speaking itself is somehow equivalent to being or to thinking and cognizing), a view which would conflict with the apparent presentation in the poem of a great many other objects of meaningful speech, such as mortals, the goddess and the various topics of Opinion.Footnote 52

Up to this point, I have argued that aspects of Parmenides’ poem which were taken by some readers, as early as Plato and as recently as Robbiano and Cherubin, to yield clashes between language and doctrine in Parmenides do not, after all, yield such clashes. Before moving on to analyse what I take to be genuine cases of such tension, I wish to highlight a final, literary weakness in the view that Parmenides contradicts Reality’s ontology whenever he deploys distinctions, uses grammatical negations or plurals, or refers to items that involve heterogeneity and change (such as humans). As we are about to see, Reality does indeed bring to our attention more specific, pointed and, in some cases, subtle conflicts between language and doctrine. If, however, Parmenides in fact contradicted Reality’s ontology through more or less everything he wrote there, whenever he strung two words together or even just one, then those more nuanced tensions would be rather drowned out.

III. Rehabilitating a case for tension

Let us turn now to passages in Reality that do after all confront us with tensions between language and doctrine. Indeed, we will see that the text repeatedly foregrounds these tensions in a more pointed and sustained manner than is generally recognized. Furthermore, we can identify these tensions independently of presuming some specific or very controversial interpretation of Parmenides’ account of Being. The cumulative effect of these passages is an interpretive puzzle that makes a claim on our attention: why does Parmenides repeatedly choose to couch certain ontological views through language that stands in stark tension with those views?

The goddess sets us on the road of Reality as follows (B8.1–4):

μόνος δ’ ἔτι μῦθος ὁδοῖο

λϵίπϵται ὡς ἔστιν· ταύτῃ δ’ ἐπὶ σήματ’ ἔασι

πολλὰ μάλ’, ὡς ἀγένητον ἐὸν καὶ ἀνώλϵθρόν ἐστιν,

οὖλον μουνογϵνές τϵ καὶ ἀτρϵμὲς † ἠδ᾽ ἀτέλϵστον †.

Only one tale of a road yet

Remains: that [it] is; and on this road there are signs

Very many, that what-is is ungenerated and imperishable,

Whole, single-born and unshaken [and complete?].

Parmenides’ talk of ‘signs’ in B8.2 is a first indication that what follows falls short of a straightforward or unproblematic articulation. Heraclitus DK22 B93 offers an instructive comparison: ‘the lord whose oracle is the one in Delphi neither says (λέγϵι) nor conceals (κρύπτϵι) but gives a sign (σημαίνϵι)’. Apollo neither speaks the answers to our questions nor takes action to prevent us from acquiring them: instead, his signs offer a starting point from which, with well-directed effort, we can gain insight and understanding concerning our inquiries.Footnote 53 The goddess’ ‘signs’ here appear to promise ‘proofs that something is the case’.Footnote 54 At the same time, from Parmenides’ characterization of what comes next as ‘signs’, we might already suspect that his discussion of what-is will amount to something other and more demanding than a direct or full spelling-out. This impression will gain further corroboration and resonance when we look back at the goddess’ talk of ‘signs’ by contradistinction with the ‘names’ that, in turn, underpin and make up the cosmology of mortals, and which are typified by both conventionality and a strong commitment on the part of speakers to the appropriateness of the language used.Footnote 55

If our suspicion is first roused by the term ‘signs’, the following words will not allay it. Lines 3–4 offer a catalogue of properties (shown by the ‘signs’) that, as the goddess will demonstrate, typify what-is. Strikingly, at least three of the terms in question are negations of properties with which we are familiar from our sensory experiences of multiple and heterogeneous things (‘un-generated’, ‘im-perishable’, ‘un-shaken’). Indeed, throughout Reality, the goddess continues to characterize what-is predominantly by working out what is not true of it.Footnote 56 Clearly, μουνογϵνές cannot be ascribing birth to what-is, and we can parallel the sense ‘-kind’ for compounds ending in -γϵνής.Footnote 57 What-is, then, is ‘of single kind’.Footnote 58 But the literal sense, ‘single-born’ (as in Hesiod, Theog. 426; Op. 376), will be the first to hit the ear, and it is notable that Parmenides resorts to this vocabulary immediately after designating what-is ‘ungenerated’ (ἀγένητον).Footnote 59 Our text for the final predicate in B8.4 is uncertain. We may read that Being is ‘not incomplete’ (οὐδ’ ἀτέλϵστον) or, alternatively, that it is ‘complete’ (ἠδὲ τέλϵιον).Footnote 60 On the former alternative, Parmenides ends the sequence with yet another alpha-privative adjective. On the latter, we conclude with a positive term, albeit an extremely vague and schematic one. Indeed, whatever Parmenides originally wrote in B8.4b, this predicate will later be expanded principally through a series of negative remarks, for example that what-is is not incomplete or in need (B8.32–33, 42–49). On the whole, we can say that, even as he introduces the project of deducing its properties, Parmenides speaks of what-is through vocabulary that is manifestly and even emphatically appropriate to other things, things that are born or otherwise come into being, perish and exhibit imperfections and needs. Parmenides’ signs already show themselves to be indirect: we begin to talk about the nature of what-is by specifying how, in different respects, it is unlike us and the items of our experiences. We appear to lack a vocabulary designed for speaking directly about what-is itself. The description of what-is as ‘single-born’ (μουνογϵνές), following close on its characterization as ‘ungenerated’ (ἀγένητον), makes us conscious in a particularly pointed way of the fact that Parmenides is deploying here language made for very different items and very different descriptive tasks.

The goddess’ first argument along the road shows that what-is never first came into being (B8.6–10).Footnote 61 After this argument is concluded, the goddess recapitulates its findings and her general principle of argumentation (B8.12–18):

οὐδέ ποτ’ ἐκ μὴ ἐόντος ἐϕήσϵι Πίστιος ἰσχύς

γίγνϵσθαί τι παρ’ αὐτό· τοῦ ϵἵνϵκϵν οὔτϵ γϵνέσθαι

οὔτ’ ὄλλυσθαι ἀνῆκϵ Δίκη χαλάσασα πέδῃσιν,

ἀλλ’ ἔχϵι· ἡ δὲ κρίσις πϵρὶ τούτων ἐν τῷδ’ ἔστιν·

ἔστιν ἢ οὐκ ἔστιν· κέκριται δ’ οὖν, ὥσπϵρ ἀνάγκη,

τὴν μὲν ἐᾶν ἀνόητον ἀνώνυμον, οὐ γὰρ ἀληθής

ἔστιν ὁδός, τὴν δ’ ὥστϵ πέλϵιν καὶ ἐτήτυμον ϵἶναι.

Nor ever from what-is-not will the strength of Trust allow

Something to come to be beside it;Footnote 62 for that reason neither to come to be

Nor to perish did Justice permit it by loosening her shackles

But she holds it fast in them. And the decision about these matters comes down to this:

[It] is or [it] is not; and so the decision has been made, as is necessary,

To leave the one road unconceived, unnamed, for it is no true

Road, but that the other road is and is genuine.

This passage does not deduce new properties for what-is. It underscores the basic principle underpinning the goddess’ argumentation: what-is must wholly exhibit being and in no way not-being; it is ‘fully’ (πάμπαν, B8.11). A first consequence of this, as was demonstrated in B8.6–10, is that it did not first come into being. What is new and striking about these lines, however, is that we are abruptly confronted with a proliferation of new figures and factors not previously encountered along the road of what-is. It is suddenly the force of Persuasion or Trust (Pistis) that will not permit something to come to be from what-is-not.Footnote 63 If one could wonder whether or not ‘trust’ is portrayed here as a personified character or an abstract logical principle, there can be no such doubt as we proceed to the anthropomorphized figure of Justice, who prevents what-is from coming into being or perishing by restraining it firmly in her shackles, the first in a series of shackle-wielding goddesses we encounter in B8.

Now, I do not doubt that, above all, this recurrent imagery provides indispensable conceptual resources for expressing the ways in which the properties of what-is are appropriate and necessary for it and thereby helps guide readers of the poem towards a proper understanding of what-is.Footnote 64 And yet, I wish to emphasize that Parmenides also develops this motif in such a way as to keep this form of expression at arm’s length and to caution us that we cannot take it at face value. In the present case, we may ask why it is, in the end, that what-is did not come into being and will not perish. Before lines B8.12–14, Parmenides answered this question through an argument that centred on the discrimination between ‘[it] is’ and ‘[it] is not’ as mutually exclusive and rejected the latter. Indeed, immediately after his remarks about Trust and Justice, Parmenides returns to the dialectical necessity imposed by this discrimination (B8.15–18). It is impossible to square this line of thought with the idea of external divine agents who, at their discretion, are acting on what-is and influencing it from the outside. The conceit that it was as a result of the logical considerations previously laid out that Justice decided to restrain what is (τοῦ ϵἵνϵκϵν … ἀνῆκϵ Δίκη, B8.13–14) only accentuates the impossibility of taking Justice’s agency at face value.Footnote 65 The most pointed aspect of the tension here between doctrine and imagery, however, is the clash between the violent and almost bestializing image of what-is as a shackled animal, or perhaps a Titan, restrained in bonds and the previous and subsequent descriptions of it as whole, unshaken, unmoved and perfected (B8.4–6, 26), as well as ‘altogether inviolate’ (πᾶν … ἄσυλον, B8.48).Footnote 66

The following lines (B8.19–21) foreground another sort of tension:

πῶς δ’ ἂν ἔπϵιτα πέλοι τὸ ἐόν; πῶς δ’ ἄν κϵ γένοιτο;

ϵἰ γὰρ ἔγϵντ’, οὐκ ἔστ’, οὐδ’ ϵἴ ποτϵ μέλλϵι ἔσϵσθαι.

τὼς γένϵσις μὲν ἀπέσβϵσται καὶ ἄπυστος ὄλϵθρος.

And how could what-is be hereafter? And how could it become?

For if it came to be, it is not, nor is it if it is going to be at some time.

Thus coming-to-be is extinguished and perishing is unheard of.

Parmenides here goes out of his way to frame his conclusions about what-is through terms whose inapplicability to what-is, and unsuitability in an account of reality, he already takes himself to have established. Being was never characterized by a coming-into-being that could be ‘extinguished’ (nor a perishing that could go unheard). In this context, it is as enticing as it is nonsensical to suggest that coming-into-being perished. Both this particular tension between language and doctrine and others discussed above resurface in the goddess’ remarks at B8.26–31:

(i) αὐτὰρ ἀκίνητον μϵγάλων ἐν πϵίρασι δϵσμῶν

ἔστιν ἄναρχον ἄπαυστον, (ii) ἐπϵὶ γένϵσις καὶ ὄλϵθρος

τῆλϵ μάλ’ ἐπλάγχθησαν, (iii) ἀπῶσϵ δὲ Πίστις ἀληθής.

(iv) ταὐτόν τ’ ἐν ταὐτῷ τϵ μένον καθ’ ἑαυτό τϵ κϵῖται

χοὔτως ἔμπϵδον αὖθι μένϵι. (v) κρατϵρὴ γὰρ Ἀνάγκη

πϵίρατος ἐν δϵσμοῖσιν ἔχϵι, τό μιν ἀμϕὶς ἐέργϵι.

(i) Further, changeless and motionless in the limits of great bonds

It is without starting, without stopping, (ii) since coming-to-be and

perishing

Wandered very far away, (iii) and true Trust pushed them off.

(iv) Remaining the same in the same by itself it lies

And so it remains there steadfast; (v) for mighty Necessity

Holds it in the bonds of a limit, which encloses it round about.

In (i), Parmenides asserts that what-is does not change or move (the language of limits and bonds recurs, but without mention of an external constraining agent), and denies it both a starting point and an end point.Footnote 67 In (ii) and (iii), he immediately proceeds to frame this latter denial through the sensory and dynamic imagery of motion and change: the fallen figures of Being’s Coming-into-Being and Perishing are forced to wander far away; true Trust reappears as the heroic figure who manages to push them off.Footnote 68 In (iv) Parmenides stresses the still permanence and steadfastly unchanging nature of Being (ταὐτόν … μένον … κϵῖται … ἔμπϵδον … μένϵι) as well as its solitary isolation and lack of outside interactions (ταὐτόν τ’ ἐν ταὐτῷ … καθ’ ἑαυτό). In (v), however, he immediately reprises the contrasting image of Being as a sort of shackled beast or titan that must be restrained in bonds (ἐν δϵσμοῖσιν), this time held firmly through the discretion and sustained or even violent effort of mighty Necessity. Once again, the logical connective attaching (v) to (iv), ‘for’ (γάρ), only accentuates the difficulty of squaring these two divergent portrayals of Being.

The imagery of binding recurs once more at B8.34–41:

(i a ) ταὐτὸν δ’ ἐστὶ νοϵῖν τϵ καὶ οὕνϵκϵν ἔστι νόημα.

(i b ) οὐ γὰρ ἄνϵυ τοῦ ἐόντος, ἐν ᾧ πϵϕατισμένον ἐστιν,

ϵὑρήσϵις τὸ νοϵῖν· (ii) οὐδὲν γὰρ <ἢ> ἔστιν ἢ ἔσται

ἄλλο πάρϵξ τοῦ ἐόντος, (iii) ἐπϵὶ τό γϵ Mοῖρ’ ἐπέδησϵν

οὖλον ἀκίνητόν τ’ ἔμϵναι· (iv) τῷ πάντ’ ὄνομ’ ἔσται,

ὅσσα βροτοὶ κατέθϵντο πϵποιθότϵς ϵἶναι ἀληθῆ,

γίγνϵσθαί τϵ καὶ ὄλλυσθαι, ϵἶναί τϵ καὶ οὐχί,

καὶ τόπον ἀλλάσσϵιν διά τϵ χρόα ϕανὸν ἀμϵίβϵιν.

(ia) The same thing is both for cognizing and that because of which there is cognition.

(ib) For not without what-is, in what has been expressed,

Will you find cognizing.Footnote 69 (ii) For nothing else either is or will be

Beside what-is, (iii) since Moira shackled it

To be whole, and changeless and motionless. (iv) All things will be its name,Footnote 70

As many as mortals established, believing them to be real,

Coming-to-be and perishing, to be and not to be,

And changing place and exchanging bright colour.

Even by Parmenides’ standards, this is an extremely dense passage. His logical connectives give us at least a broad view of the goddess’ inferential moves here. (iii) justifies (ii). What-is is a unified whole that does not change (iii); therefore, what-is will never create something other than, or in addition to, itself; given, moreover, that nothing else could come into being from what-is-not (as was established before), what-is is all there is and there will never be anything other than what-is (ii). In turn, (ii) justifies (i). What-is is all there is (ii), and so what-is is the only object of the thinking and apprehension of which the goddess speaks here (i).Footnote 71 In addition, (ii) can plausibly be taken to justify (iv). What-is is all there is (ii), and so the various misguided labels that mortals try to pin on reality (πϵποιθότϵς ϵἶναι ἀληθῆ, B8.39) must in fact have what-is as their true referent (iv).

To be sure, this outline raises questions. Some would infer from the restriction of being to what-is (B8.36–37) that only what-is exists, although this would make nonsense of the goddess’ subsequent claim that mortals make errors about reality, and indeed of the very possibility of the goddess and the kouros (seemingly) conversing. Alternatively, as outlined above, we may follow Plutarch’s lead (Mor. 1114d–e) and take it that Parmenides reserves the term ‘being’ for what-is since it alone exemplifies being perfectly and without qualification. On this line of thought, it is for this reason that, as (i) suggests, what-is alone is the proper object of proper cognition or understanding and amenable to the true, steadfast and reliable apprehension reflected through the arguments of Reality, and that, as (iv) indicates, what-is is de facto the only possible referent for names that purport to disclose the ultimate reality (πϵποιθότϵς ϵἶναι ἀληθῆ, B8.39).Footnote 72

The central point of interest for us, however, is the introduction of Moira. The sudden appearance of this final goddess here is a far from obvious or unsurprising choice. Parmenides had already taken himself to have earned, or at least to afford, the points that what-is is a unified whole (οὖλον) that is unmoving and unchanging (ἀκίνητον). He might have recapitulated those points here without introducing the constrictive influence of yet another ostensibly external divine force.Footnote 73 Moira is, moreover, at once a precisely appropriate and precisely inappropriate figure for the task of rendering what-is ‘whole’. On the one hand, Moira apportions to each thing its due lot in the world, and it is the suitable lot of what-is to be whole and unchanging. On the other hand, the term μοῖρα itself means ‘part’, ‘division’ and ‘distribution’, and the goddess Moira incarnates division.Footnote 74 The suggestion that division renders reality whole, a quality that Parmenides elsewhere describes in terms of indivisibility (οὐδὲ διαιρϵτόν, B8.22), pulls us up short. In (iv), Parmenides next proceeds to consider the various categories or ‘names’, like ‘coming-to-be and perishing’, which mortals wrongly think capture truly the structure of reality. And yet, the weakness of mortal names only draws attention to the goddess’ own immediately preceding and jarringly dissonant appeal to the figure of Moira. Furthermore, we cannot overemphasize the point that, although Parmenides precisely refuses to accept their conceptual scheme as apt for mapping out the nature of true reality, the terms in which the wayward mortals wrongly place their trust (B8.38–41) are the same terms through which the goddess communicates with Parmenides, and Parmenides with us, when they describe what-is as without generation (γίγνϵσθαι) or perishing (ὄλλυσθαι) or motion (τόπον ἀλλάσσϵιν). In describing what-is, the goddess does not supplant the names that mortals established with some alternative set of names. Rather, she proceeds, in a largely indirect and negative manner, by demonstrating the inapplicability to what-is of the mortal names themselves. Parmenides continues to speak the mortal language, even as he cautions us that its categories cannot directly articulate the nature of what-is.Footnote 75 In section IV, we will revisit the point that, in speaking this language, Parmenides not only resorts to such rudimentary terms (‘ungenerated’, ‘imperishable’, etc.) for expressing the attributes of what-is, but also introduces the elaborate imagery of the external application of force by Moira and the other shackle-wielding goddesses.

We should not work too hard to fit every aspect or passage of Reality into the pattern of tension between language and doctrine that we already found to be exemplified amply in B8. One important possible exception is the goddess’ repeated insistence that what-is is. With the ascription of ‘being’ to what-is, if nowhere else, we may find a use of language in relation to what-is that the goddess puts forward without pointed indications that she is holding her expressions at arm’s length. Indeed, B6.1 likely enjoins us to say (and to understand) that Being is.Footnote 76 It is possible, although our evidence nowhere conclusively frames things in this way, that we are invited to think of (τὸ) ἐόν as the name whose denotation is the entity whose properties are worked out in B8.Footnote 77 Even here, though, things are not entirely straightforward. Side by side with this technical use of the verb ‘to be’ in relation to what-is,Footnote 78 we also unsurprisingly find Parmenides using this verb in a more everyday sense, and in relation to everyday (generated, perishable, internally articulated, heterogeneous) things, as for example in his remark that the wayward mortals ‘are’ in a state of having erred (πϵπλανημένοι ϵἰσίν, B8.54).Footnote 79 I see no strong reason to think that, through this and other such uses of the verb ‘to be’, Parmenides is (here too) calling attention to the pitfalls and limitations of human language. At the same time, his everyday and indeed loose or catachrestic uses of the term should make us sympathetic to the worry (a worry that I have been arguing Parmenides evinces throughout Reality) that the exigencies of human language make it an inadequate vehicle for spelling out directly or straightforwardly the goddess’ ontological doctrine, a doctrine according to which it is only what-is that can unqualifiedly and properly speaking be said to be.Footnote 80

Also worthy of comment in this connection is the fact that Parmenides several times uses πέλϵιν, a term that, elsewhere, often indicates dynamic processes of becoming and connotes a sense of motion, as a functional equivalent of the verb ‘to be’.Footnote 81 While this usage of πέλϵιν is not uncommon in early Greek poetry, its occurrence within a context that repeatedly draws our attention to the dissonance between the ontological message and the language and imagery used to convey it makes it at least possible to find here another such gesture. Most notable is Parmenides’ use of the term as a substitute for ϵἶναι (and the opposite of οὐκ ϵἶναι) when expounding the aimless wandering of the wayward mortals:

… that road on which indeed mortals who know nothing stray double-headed (πλάζονται δίκρανοι), for helplessness guides the wandering mind (πλαγκτὸν νόον) in their breasts, and they are borne along (ϕορϵῦνται) deaf and blind alike in bewilderment, a tribe without discrimination, by whom to be and not to be have been deemed the same and not the same (οἷς τὸ πέλϵιν τϵ καὶ οὐκ ϵἶναι ταὐτὸν νϵνόμισται κοὐ ταὐτόν). (B6.4–9)

In this context, rich with imagery of constant fluctuation and movement, the term πέλϵιν can plausibly be seen to underscore a linguistic aspect of the error of the mortals. The human confusion about the nature of Being is reflected through both the formal contradiction in lines 8–9 (‘the same and not the same’) and the readiness of human language (a language that Parmenides too continues to speak) to refer to Being through a term redolent with connotations of becoming and movement. In B8.18, πέλϵιν, alongside ϵἶναι, indicates that the first road, the road that [it] is, ‘is and is genuine’ (πέλϵιν καὶ ἐτήτυμον ϵἶναι). In the very next line, πέλϵιν is used to ask ‘how could what-is be hereafter’ (πῶς δ’ ἂν ἔπϵιτα πέλοι τὸ ἐόν), a usage that converges on the sense ‘become’ and, indeed, forms a hendiadys with the question that closes the line: ‘how could it become?’ (πῶς δ’ ἄν κϵ γένοιτο, B8.19).Footnote 82 Later in Reality, Parmenides remarks: ‘from the middle equally advanced in all directions (μϵσσόθϵν ἰσοπαλὲς πάντῃ), for it must not be (πϵλέναι) either at all greater or at all smaller here or there’ (B8.44–45). Regarding ἰσοπαλές, Alexander Mourelatos observes ‘the dynamic connotation of the root παλ-’ (he renders ἰσοπαλές ‘pushing out equally’, ‘equally advanced’) and later also marks the alliterative effect with πϵλέναι.Footnote 83 We may add that this alliteration brings out, and is itself accentuated by, the dynamic connotations of πϵλέναι itself, and that in the case of both ἰσοπαλές and πϵλέναι the dynamic connotation is starkly at odds with the stability and changelessness of the equal distribution of what-is that these terms express here.Footnote 84

This last couplet comes from Parmenides’ well-known description of what-is as ‘complete’ (τϵτϵλϵσμένον) and ‘like the bulk of a well-rounded ball’ (ϵὐκύκλου σϕαίρης ἐναλίγκιον ὄγκῳ, B8.42–49). A proper consideration of this complex passage will take us too far off course, but the central interpretive alternatives can be usefully delineated. In the end, we should keep an open mind concerning the import of this analogy to our question. Some scholars infer from these lines that what-is is a spatially extended sphere. It is reasonably pointed out that, grammatically, the phrase μϵσσόθϵν ἰσοπαλὲς πάντῃ (B8.44) is said of what-is rather than the ball or its bulk.Footnote 85 Others read the passage figuratively. Mourelatos, for example, insists that Parmenides does not draw an analogy between what-is and a ball but, rather, between the completeness of what-is and the expanse of a well-rounded ball (τϵτϵλϵσμένον ἐστί … σϕαίρης ἐναλίγκιον ὄγκῳ). He sees the passage’s criteria for the sphere’s uniformity and completeness or perfection as standing in for criteria of uniformity and completeness in general. In this light, the remark that what-is is ‘from the middle equally advanced in all directions’ becomes not the assertion that Being is a literal sphere but an attempt to convey the idea of perfect completeness and uniformity.Footnote 86 On the literal view, we seem to find in B8.42–49 one respect in which our language and conceptual repertoire allow us to articulate directly one aspect of what-is (its physical shape) and, as such, something of an exception to the general trend we found in Reality. On the figurative view, we find here yet another example of Parmenides’ need to resort to inevitably imperfect linguistic and imagistic devices that are drawn from very different conceptual domains in order to construct his description of what-is.

Whatever view one takes of the sphere passage, it is clear by now that this project of describing what-is is one for which, by and large, Parmenides does not have quite the right words. He repeatedly brings this predicament to our attention both by underscoring the predominantly negative and indirect means by which his description of what-is proceeds and by foregrounding other terminology and elaborate imagery that sit ill at ease, sometimes pointedly so, with the very views this language is used to convey. The question, then, is why Parmenides does so. What is the point of the tensions between language and doctrine that pervade the Way of Reality?

IV. Conclusions

In the proem, the goddess remarks that the youth has travelled ‘far from the track of humans’ (B1.27). Later she encourages him to resist letting ‘habit born of much experience’ (B7.3) force him onto the road of wayward mortals. And yet, though what-is represents an unfamiliar and strange object of inquiry and knowledge, the goddess continues throughout to communicate to the youth about it in the language of mortals. It is appropriate, then, that, time and again and in a variety of ways, Parmenides reflects his awareness that the language he uses to give an account of what-is, and to guide our minds towards an apprehension and understanding of it, has been imported with difficulty from its natural domain, in which it is put to very different uses and in relation to very different objects. As highlighted in the introduction, my suggestion is not that we can tease out from Parmenides’ fragments an elaborated theory on the workings and limits of human language, or that this was a primary focus of his efforts. What we can more modestly glean in Parmenides, however, is a reflective preoccupation with, and a consistent and self-aware attitude towards, the scope, orientation and limitations of human language, a preoccupation and attitude that have important philosophical consequences.Footnote 87

Parmenides takes himself to be arguing conclusively for a particular view about the nature of Being, and to place us in a position to ascertain for ourselves the truth of this view. And yet, this idea of Being is one that cannot be articulated in a full, direct or straightforward way. We can (perhaps) say that what-is is without evincing any reservation concerning our form of expression. But as soon as we try to go beyond this bare point, and to put into words the nature of what-is, we find ourselves straining against the expressive limits of our language. The description of what-is in Reality is ultimately restricted to a small number of schematic characterizations. This constrained aspect of Reality is especially marked by contrast with the richer and detailed descriptions in the Way of Opinion (as even our meagre extant evidence allows us to say) of the multiple and heterogeneous items of our everyday experience (B8.53–19).

It might be objected that the predicates deduced in Reality for what-is exhaust the nature of what-is. That is, it might be objected that, perhaps once we say that what-is is ungenerated, imperishable, unchanging and immobile, evenly distributed (that is, not more or less here or there: B8.44–45), all alike and indivisible, etc. (possibly including: spatially extended in the shape of a sphere), we have given a full account of its nature. If so, then our conceptual scheme can even be said to do a perfect job of capturing and articulating the nature of what-is. As we have seen, however, even these few characteristics are by and large expressed negatively and indirectly, by denying to what-is qualities that characterize multiple and heterogeneous things.Footnote 88 What-is, we learn, is un-generated, im-perishable, in-divisible, un-shaken, un-moving, and so on. As we build our understanding of what-is, we repeatedly find ourselves forced to discuss it through a language that is clearly designed for expressing altogether different things, the generated, perishable, divisible, changing, mobile, multiple and heterogeneous items of everyday experience. Indeed, this is the very same language in whose aptness for articulating reality wayward mortals wrongly place their trust (B8.38–41), and through which Parmenides and his goddess continue to communicate about what-is. We may also note how, by contrast with this prevalent tendency of Reality, in Opinion Parmenides is better able to call on positive characteristics, familiar from lived experience, so as to introduce and describe directly the properties of the two cosmological elements: ‘the aethereal fire of flame, being gentle, extremely light … night unknowing,Footnote 89 dense and heavy in body’ (ϕλογὸς αἰθέριον πῦρ | ἤπιον ὄν, μέγ’ ἐλαϕρόν … νύκτ’ ἀδαῆ, πυκινὸν δέμας ἐμβριθές τϵ, B8.56–59). It makes little difference (and it is impossible to determine) if it is intrinsic to what-is that it largely resists direct expression or if it merely resists direct expression through human language, for we possess no other. Parmenides’ proclivity for negative formulations especially claims our attention in the wake of Xenophanes, whose account of his Greatest God is echoed in Parmenides’ account of what-is and whose theological remarks, in recognition of the way in which our perspective is constrained by our experiences (DK21 B34), tend to stipulate negatively what the gods are not like.Footnote 90

It is in this context that we should view the especially marked cases of tension between language and doctrine in Reality. Parmenides not only describes what-is in a largely negative and indirect manner, but also repeatedly introduces elaborate language and imagery that is pointedly and precisely dissonant with its nature (as, for example, with ‘Moira’ and the imagery of shackles applied from the outside by anthropomorphized goddesses). In doing so, Parmenides alerts us to the general inappropriateness of our language for an articulation of what-is.Footnote 91 Put differently, the problematic and elaborate mythological imagery flags up what the fundamental and perhaps more inevitable negative descriptions also repeatedly convey in their own way: that, time and again, we are straining to describe the nature of what-is through a language that is ill-suited to the task of expressing this nature and that was developed for dealing with other things. By alerting us to the limitations of his language and imagery, Parmenides prescribes for us general vigilance when it comes to the business of using language as a tool with which to work our way towards an understanding of what-is. By deploying some descriptions of what-is that are very precisely dissonant with its nature and could not be taken literally, Parmenides impels us to ask what we can take away from any discursive account of what-is unreservedly and what we must keep at arm’s length.Footnote 92

None of these conclusions denies that the goddess offers a description of what-is. It is difficult to see how else we might classify remarks like ‘Being is ungenerated and imperishable’ (ἀγένητον ἐὸν καὶ ἀνώλϵθρόν ἐστιν, B8.3) or ‘it is all alike’ (πᾶν ἐστιν ὁμοῖον, B8.22) and, in general, the goddess’ extended delineation of the characteristics of Being in B8.Footnote 93 Parmenides does, however, evince and encourage an awareness that this description proceeds through expressive measures that are imported with difficulty from a very different domain and are, consequently, limited, indirect and often figurative. We can usefully contrast here the unreserved and committed attitude that wayward mortals take towards their ‘names’. They establish names like ‘coming-to-be and perishing’, ‘changing place’ and ‘exchanging bright colour’ and see these as categories that capture the nature of reality truly and faithfully (πϵποιθότϵς ϵἶναι ἀληθῆ, B8.38–41). That mortals’ names represent something stronger and more committal than the mere labelling of an item is again clear when the goddess diagnoses their decision to ‘name’ Light and Night as their cardinal error (B8.53–54; cf. B19).Footnote 94 Parmenides’ attitude towards the vocabulary that underpins his account in Reality, and which includes prominently and throughout terms like ‘becoming’, ‘perishing’, ‘motion’ and ‘change’, must be viewed in relation to his overt critiques of mortal names and especially of mortals’ blithe acquiescence and misplaced trust in the presumption that these names map onto the nature of reality faithfully. The goddess, by marked contrast, nowhere expresses comparable commitment to the different linguistic terms and categories that make up her account of what-is in Reality. On the contrary, the attitude of the mortals contrasts with her more guarded, elusive and indirect framing of what she proffers in Reality as ‘signs’ (B8.2–3).Footnote 95

Can we, then, frame those aspects of Parmenides’ language that conflict with his ontology as a ladder he climbs and then throws away?Footnote 96 There are two divergent problems with this metaphor. On the one hand, if the view defended here concerning what should and should not count as genuine conflict between language and doctrine in Reality is on the right lines, then the ladder metaphor overstates Parmenides’ argumentative reliance on dissonant language. Moira and the other anthropomorphized shackling goddesses play an important role in conceptualizing the appropriateness and necessity of the nature of what-is; but their role is throughout no more or less than that of a figurative conceptual resource: the argumentation at no stage requires us to treat this imagery of external shackling (or the other discordant imagery we have identified) literally or at face value.Footnote 97 We also saw that this imagery is more than once introduced to offer a new way of representing and thinking about properties of what-is that Parmenides had already established or affirmed without it. On the other hand, the ladder metaphor understates our inexorable dependence on a conceptual framework that can only make up a description of what-is indirectly and with difficulty and that we could never discard. The goddess enables the youth, and Parmenides enables us, to grasp and understand (νοϵῖν) what what-is is like only by deploying, and denying to what-is, such concepts as generation, perishing, internal divisions, change and mobility, and indeed by resorting further to mythological language that cannot be taken at face value. There is no suggestion in the poem of some further stage of initiation in which we will be able simply to dispense with this conceptual scheme and review or retrace the nature of Being without it. Where the ladder metaphor does point us in the right direction is in its suggestion that the value of human language to ontological inquiry is strictly heuristic. Our language is useful to us in this context, not insofar as it can directly articulate the nature of Being as it does with such things as stars or humans (it cannot), but as a tool with which to work towards an apprehension of the nature of Being and to place ourselves in the appropriate frame of mind to contemplate it.Footnote 98

The Parmenides who emerged above anticipates to a meaningful but still partial extent the later Platonic idea that the One is ineffable. Plotinus writes that we cannot ascribe any predicates to the One, since this would turn it into a multiplicity of subject and predicates (Enn. 5.3.10). Consequently, we cannot in fact say anything of the One but only use language as an imperfect heuristic device in relation to it, or: ‘make signs to ourselves’ about it (ἡμῖν αὐτοῖς σημαίνϵιν, Enn. 5.3.13.5). We largely develop some awareness of the One by differentiating it from the world of complexity and multiplicity that, in Plotinus’ scheme, comes after the One and is causally reliant on it; that is, we develop an awareness of the One through negation (Enn. 5.3.14). Plotinus emphasizes that Platonists speak about the One as they do because it is impossible to speak about it as they wish. He cautions that the qualification ‘as if’ should be assumed to apply to every statement about the One (Enn. 6.8.13; 6.8.18.52–53). He repeatedly helps himself to metaphors and images (such as the famous comparison of the One and the world order dependent on it to a king’s triumphal procession), which inevitably involve both illuminating points of contact and misleading discontinuities between the source domain of the metaphor and the target domain of the One (Enn. 5.5.3; 6.8.9).Footnote 99

To be sure, there are notable divergences between Parmenides and Plotinus on this score. First, Parmenides does not seem to regard what-is as wholly ineffable. If nothing else, we can assert seemingly without reservation that what-is is. Second, Parmenides remains adamant that what-is can be the object of intellectual apprehension (νοϵῖν), whereas for Plotinus the One cannot even be an object of thought and understanding but only somehow received through a kind of ‘touching’, free of speech or thought (Enn. 5.3.10.41–42). A third and related difference is that Parmenides nowhere evinces a similarly exacting notion of radical simplicity that precludes even the having of a conceptual structure nor, therefore, any discomfort with thinking of Being as having properties. Indeed, it is Plotinus’ distinctive refusal to think of the One as a property-bearing entity (a ‘this’) that leads him to describe it as ‘beyond being’ (Enn. 5.5.6; cf. 5.1.10.2; 6.8.9.27–28).

These divergences notwithstanding, Parmenides too evinces the awareness that what-is resists unproblematic or direct expression through language and that, in the context of ontological inquiry, language is thus useful to us only as an imperfect heuristic device with which to work our way towards an apprehension of what-is and its properties, indirectly and with difficulty. Parmenides can fairly be described as a forerunner to the later Platonic idea that the key philosophical and metaphysical principle is something we cannot quite put into the only words at our disposal.

Acknowledgements

This article was improved considerably by questions and comments from the two anonymous reviewers and the editor and (in 2018 and 2019) from audiences in London and San Diego. I am also indebted to discussions with Matthew Evans and Benjamin Folit-Weinberg and to Victoria Wohl, who kindly shared with me her work-in-progress on the role of metaphors in Parmenides. Special thanks are due to Jenny Strauss Clay for multiple valuable discussions and for sharing with me work-in-progress that approaches Parmenides in a similar spirit to this article. Though we took somewhat different Parmenidean routes (her own discussions focus more on the proem and the cosmology), we arrived at congruent conclusions.

Funding Statement

This article was written during a period of leave funded by the Leverhulme Trust, for whose support I am grateful.

Footnotes

1 On Plato’s Sophist, see section II below. Except where otherwise noted, references to Parmenides (and other early Greek philosophers) are to the Diels–Kranz edition. Translations are my own, but translations of Parmenides draw freely on Coxon (Reference Coxon, McKirahan and Schofield2009), Palmer (Reference Palmer2009), Graham (Reference Graham2010) and Laks and Most (Reference Kraus, Frank and Giombini2016).

2 For example, Woodbury (Reference Weiss1971); (Reference Woodbury, Anton and Kustas1986); Owens (Reference Owens, Mansfeld and de Rijk1975); Graeser (Reference Gianvittorio1977a); (Reference Graeser1977b); Calvo (Reference Calvo1977); Kraus (Reference Kraus1987) 57–97; (Reference Kraus, Frank and Giombini2019); Škiljan (Reference Škiljan1998), especially 20–21; Barrett (Reference Barrett2004); Vlastos (Reference Vlastos and Mourelatos2008); Palmer (Reference Palmer2009) 167–74; Marcinkowska-Rosół (Reference Marcinkowska-Rosół2010) 53–59, 80–91, 128–30, 139–50; Gianvittorio (Reference Gianvittorio2013); Tor (Reference Tor2017) 203–08; Bernabé (Reference Bernabé, Frank and Giombini2019a); Pulpito (Reference Pulpito, Frank and Giombini2019); Di Iulio (Reference Di Iulio2021); Mansfeld (Reference Mansfeld2021) 211–16. It would be arbitrary to make any selection from the numerous further discussions devoted to certain lines in Reality that make (or have been taken to make) some reference to speaking (B2.7–8 (but see in section II on ϕράσαις); B6.1; 8.7–9, 34–36). These lines are addressed below, although they are not the focus of this article.

3 Some important exceptions addressed below: Owen (Reference Owen1960) 100; (Reference Owen1966) 321–22; Furth (Reference Furth1968) 131–32; Mason (Reference Mason1988); Morgan (Reference Morgan2000) 67–87; Robbiano (Reference Robbiano2016) 275–82; (Reference Robbiano2018); Cherubin (Reference Cherubin2017); (Reference Cherubin2018).

4 I refer interchangeably to The Way of Reality and Reality, and to the Way of Opinion and Opinion. I refer to τὸ ἐόν interchangeably as ‘what-is’ and ‘Being’.

5 On this point I disagree with the important and stimulating arguments of Cherubin (Reference Cherubin2017); (Reference Cherubin2018).

6 It is not thereby an ambition of this article to contend that the goddess’ arguments in B8 are valid or strong. Rather, one of its aims is to defend the restricted claim that the goddess’ introduction of language and imagery that is in tension with her conclusions does not itself undermine her argumentation.

7 Mason (Reference Mason1988) and Robbiano (Reference Robbiano2016) 275–82 and (Reference Robbiano2018) maintain that no coherent reference to or account of what-is can be achieved through language and deny wholesale that Reality offers ‘a description of the characteristics of being’ (Robbiano (Reference Robbiano2018) 38; cf. Mason (Reference Mason1988) 163–64 and passim). My own conclusion that our language is not apt for an unproblematic or direct expression of what-is has affinities with, but is more qualified than, this position. Furthermore, both Mason and Robbiano (however else their accounts differ) reach their conclusions on the basis of the reasoning that, since language refers and describes through distinctions, it cannot coherently refer to or describe the undivided what-is. I offer a critical evaluation of this line of thought in section II.

8 For an unusually overt expression of this attitude, see Curd (Reference Curd2015) no. 31: ‘my suspicion/suggestion makes … [Parmenides] less obviously a Platonist, which I take to be a good thing’. Cordero (Reference Cordero and Cordero2011) 100 diagnoses the disease ‘Platonitis’ in interpretations that, in his estimation, fail to keep Parmenides sufficiently removed from Platonic thought.

9 Against such attempts, see Bryan (Reference Bryan2020a) 229; see also Folit-Weinberg (Reference Folit-Weinberg2022) 275–78.

10 Equally, by denying that the goddess’ (anthropomorphizing, mythological) imagery undermines her inferential moves, I am not denying that this imagery has philosophical import, and indeed this article explores one aspect of this import.

11 For discussions of the passage, see McCabe (Reference McCabe2000) 66–72; Castagnoli (Reference Castagnoli2010) 218–22.

12 Parmenides is, furthermore, named and cited at Soph. 244e2–5. On these passages, see Mansfeld (Reference Mansfeld2019) nos 8–15, 21. On the apparent influence of Melissus on the presentation of Parmenides in Plato, see Mansfeld (Reference Mansfeld and Pulpito2016) 85–87; (Reference Mansfeld2019) nos 9–11; Brémond (Reference Brémond2017) 158–59. Cf. Isoc. Antid. 268: Παρμϵνίδης δὲ καὶ Mέλισσος ἕν.

13 ἀποκρινέσθων (244b9), ἀπόκρισις (244c3), ἀποκρίνασθαι (244c6).

14 Cf. Cra. 388b13–c1: a name is a tool for distinguishing the essence of different things (διακριτικὸν τῆς οὐσίας), as a shuttle is a tool for dividing warp and woof.

15 Palmer (Reference Palmer1999) 166–73 reads the argument as targeting rather a predicational monist who maintains that each thing can be ascribed only its one proper predicate (for example, ‘the person is a person’). But why would it then be problematic for the interlocutor that even a single name will involve a distinction between name and referent (244d3–4, with d6–13 elaborating the absurdities that would result from collapsing the distinction between name and referent)? Nonetheless, my use here of this passage from the Sophist neither requires nor precludes agreeing with Palmer (Reference Palmer1999) 145, 173 that it does not ‘[represent] Plato’s considered view of Parmenides at this time’.

16 Cherubin (Reference Cherubin2017); (Reference Cherubin2018). Plato’s Eleatic Stranger and Cherubin concur that the tensions between Reality’s stances and the language through which they are communicated undercut those stances. While for the Stranger this is a blunder, however, for Cherubin it is a point that Parmenides wishes us to see. For a self-consciously aporetic and un-dogmatic Parmenides, see also Mackenzie (Reference Macé and Horky1982). I address this view below.

17 Cherubin (Reference Cherubin2017) 257; cf. Owen (Reference Owen1960) 100.

18 A similar point applies to the objection from time. Cherubin (Reference Cherubin2017) 255–57 takes B8.5–6 (‘but not ever was it nor yet will it be, since it now is all together, one, continuous’) to exclude temporal processes, which inquiry and argumentation necessitate. But, even if what-is is somehow outside the framework of time, it does not follow that so are other things (like humans). Furthermore, Schofield (Reference Schofield1970) makes a strong case for taking B8.5–6 as only ruling out that what-is could be subject to perishing or becoming: it is not the case that what-is existed in the past (but not now) or will exist one day (but not yet). The argumentation in the following lines fits with Schofield’s deflationary interpretation but offers nothing like a justification for the timelessness of what-is.

19 On Parmenides’ use of ἀληθϵίη and ἀληθής primarily in the sense ‘reality’ and the ‘real’, and his alignment of ‘reality’ with what-is, see Cole (Reference Cole1983) 25–26; Coxon (Reference Coxon, McKirahan and Schofield2009) 282–83; Palmer (Reference Palmer2009) 89–93 (on B1.29–30; 2.4; 8.17–18, 28, 50–51). For interpretations (with some differing modulations) of Parmenides’ ontology along the general lines sketched above, see Plut. Mor. 1114d–e = Coxon (Reference Coxon, McKirahan and Schofield2009) testim. 113; Simp. in Cael. 7.557.20–558.17 = Coxon (Reference Coxon, McKirahan and Schofield2009) testim. 203; Johansen (Reference Johansen2016); Tor (Reference Tor2017) 295–303. For a variety of other permissive ontological models, see de Rijk (Reference de Rijk and Gerson1983); Palmer (Reference Palmer2009) 45–188; Thanassas (Reference Thanassas and Cordero2011); Sisko and Weiss (Reference Sisko and Weiss2015); Rossetti (Reference Rossetti, Galgano, Giombini and Marcacci2020); Ferro (Reference Ferro, Galgano, Giombini and Marcacci2020). The once-standard strict interpretation is not without its current adherents; for example, Wedin (Reference Warren2014).

20 ‘Illusions’: Owen (Reference Owen1960) 89; Furth (Reference Furth1968) 130; Tarán (Reference Tarán1965) 230; Sedley (Reference Sedley and Long1999) 117.

21 Another difficulty for strict interpreters is that while the items of everyday experience fail to exhibit the properties of what-is, they also could not be classified as what-is-not, which is indescribable and devoid of properties and, unlike them, unavailable for inquiry (B1.28; 2.6–8; 10.4; see further in this section). For objections to the strict interpretation along these lines, see Palmer (Reference Palmer2009) 181–83; Tor (Reference Tor2017) 287–89.

23 For the positive programmatic framing of Reality, cf. also B1.29–30; 2.4; 8.1–2, 15–18. Just what the ‘deceptiveness’ (B8.51–52) of Opinion and its lack of ‘real trust’ (B1.30) amount to is uncertain. For the view that Opinion’s theories are deceptive, not qua accounts of their proper subject matter, but in their potential to be mistaken for accounts of reality, see Nehamas (Reference Nehamas, Caston and Graham2002) 59; Johansen (Reference Johansen2016) 20; Tor (Reference Tor2017) 199–202. On Opinion’s lack of ‘real trust’, see also Palmer (Reference Palmer2009) 92, 167–75. For other objections to Cherubin, see Weiss (Reference Wedin2018).

25 This concern is prominent in Mason (Reference Marcinkowska-Rosół1988).

26 Similarly, Coxon (Reference Coxon, McKirahan and Schofield2009) 21–22 sees the relation between Being and its predicates as one of identity: the different predicates refer to Being under different descriptions. He observes (pp. 22, 31–33) that predication and identity statements were not yet clearly demarcated in the Archaic period; see also Kraus (Reference Kraus1987) 67; Sattler (Reference Sattler2020) 64–65. I do not believe that σήματα at B8.2 (see section III) licenses us to see remarks like ἀνώλϵθρόν ἐστιν as somehow not ascribing properties to Being (although, again, such predications need not thereby import non-identity); contrast Sattler (Reference Sattler2020) 102, 115. On the divergence from Plotinus’ discomfort with subject-predicate statements about the One, see section IV.

27 Cherubin (Reference Cherubin2017) 253 and passim.

28 On Doxa’s two elements as such opposites, see Curd (Reference Curd1998) 107–08.

29 Reality’s krisis: B7.5–6 (κρῖναι δὲ λόγῳ); 8.15–16 (ἡ δὲ κρίσις πϵρὶ τούτων ἐν τῷδ’ ἔστιν· | ἔστιν ἢ οὐκ ἔστιν). Opinion’s krisis: B8.55–56 (ἀντία δ’ ἐκρίναντο δέμας); cf. 6.7 (ἄκριτα ϕῦλα). On the qualitative difference between the two kriseis, cf. Mansfeld (Reference Mansfeld1964) 86–91, 133; Kraus (Reference Kraus1987) 88.

30 For example, Cherubin (Reference Cherubin2017) 254; cf. Owen (Reference Owen1960) 100; (Reference Owen1966) 321–22; Furth (Reference Furth1968) 131–32 (‘Parmenides makes constant use of expressions that on his own principles are meaningless—“is not”, “nothing”, etc.’); Mason (Reference Mason1988) 153 (‘the goddess may indeed seem to “say a good deal about what cannot be said”’); Morgan (Reference Morgan2000) 83.

31 For an entirely different way of reaching this verdict (predicated on a different interpretation of Parmenides’ strictures), see Austin (Reference Austin1986) 11–43.

32 Mourelatos (Reference Mourelatos2008) 20 n.28; Svenbro (Reference Svenbro and Lloyd1993) 15–17. See Hom. Od. 1.273 (μῦθον), Od. 11.22 (indicating a destination: ἐς χῶρον … ὃν ϕράσϵ Κίρκη), Od. 15.424 (displaying a house: ἐπέϕραδϵν ὑψϵρϵϕὲς δῶ), Od. 19.250; through speech or writing: Eur. IT 760–65; by contrast with saying: Aesch. Ag. 1061; Hdt. 4.113.

33 On ἀνυστόν, see Mourelatos (Reference Mourelatos1979) 9; Curd (Reference Curd2015) no. 10.

34 Furth (Reference Furth1968) 124–28; Graeser (Reference Gianvittorio1977a) 146–47.

35 Mourelatos (Reference Mourelatos2008) 74–80 and (Reference Mourelatos1979) 9–10, followed by Curd (Reference Curd1998) 49–50 and Sanders (Reference Sanders2002) 102–03.

36 For this objection, see similarly Robbiano (Reference Robbiano2016) 269 n.16.

37 For this point, see similarly Marcinkowska-Rosół (Reference Marcinkowska-Rosół2010) 55.

38 On the absence in Parmenides of a neat distinction between complete (existential and non-predicative) and incomplete (predicative and non-existential) senses of ϵἶναι, see especially Brown (Reference Brown1986) 54–57, 69; (Reference Brown and Everson1994) 216–20.

39 See also the progression in B8.7–12 (ἐκ μὴ ἐόντος … τοῦ μηδϵνὸς … ἐκ μὴ ἐόντος). For what-is-not as what is not anything at all, cf. Kahn (Reference Kahn1969) 716; Ketchum (Reference Ketchum1990) 171–73; Palmer (Reference Palmer2009) 101–04 (but taking ‘what-is-not’ as shorthand for ‘what-is-not-and-must-not-be’); Sattler (Reference Sattler2020) 98–100. Sanders (Reference Sanders2002) 104 reads against the grain when he claims ‘a fundamental difference in meaning’ between ‘what-is-not’ and ‘nothing’.

40 Consequently, when the goddess describes things like Light and Night, humans or locomotion, or when mortals mistakenly present such things as true reality, they are not indicating or displaying what-is-not. They are not doing what in Reality the goddess pronounces impossible (contrast Di Iulio (Reference Di Iulio2021) 205–07 with n.1, 213–14 with n.12, 225). Such things possess properties incompatible with those of what-is, but they do possess properties. Thus, they are not nothing at all and indeed, unlike what-is-not, can be inquired into (B1.28–30; B10), grasped (B10) and displayed through an account (B10–19). This is why such things can be designated neither simply as ‘being’ nor as ‘not-being’.

41 On this point, cf. Sanders (Reference Sanders2002) 102.

42 I borrow the analogy with the ‘round square’ from Palmer (Reference Palmer2009) 101–03, although he pursues it in different directions.

43 Vlastos (Reference Vlastos and Mourelatos2008) 383–84 expresses a broadly similar approach (using similar mathematical analogies) to what-is-not: ‘Of such terms [sc. like Not-Being] we would certainly wish to say that they are inconceivable, meaning that no viable concept of this sort can be constructed … Yet neither would we wish to say that they are meaningless noises, since we do understand what they mean well enough to reason about them’.

44 Cornford (Reference Cornford1939) 34; Owen (Reference Owen1960) 15; Furth (Reference Furth1968) 121; Graeser (Reference Gianvittorio1977a) 148; (Reference Graeser1977b) 362–65; Nussbaum (Reference Nussbaum1979) 70; Gallop (Reference Gallop1984) 12; Kraus (Reference Kraus1987) 73; this claim is less widespread today, but see for example Lampe (Reference Lampe and Wolfsdorf2020) 115 (‘being sets the parameters for meaningful thinking and speaking’). This view has not often been subject to direct criticism, but see Mason (Reference Mason1988) 151–52 and Palmer (Reference Palmer2009) 76–82, who (in different ways) reject it as an imposition of 20th-century preoccupations about meaningfulness and meaninglessness.

45 See similarly, Mason (Reference Mason1988) 150–52; also Vlastos (Reference Vlastos and Mourelatos2008) 367–71; Di Iulio (Reference Di Iulio2021).

46 As Mansfeld (Reference Mansfeld1999) 331–33 argues; cf. Marcinkowska-Rosół (Reference Marcinkowska-Rosół2010) 86–87; Robbiano (Reference Robbiano2016) 279–80.

47 Taking τὸ λέγϵιν τὸ νοϵῖν τ’ as articular infinitives (or a compound articular infinitive, if we follow the common emendation τ<ϵ> νοϵῖν, cf. Palmer (Reference Palmer2009) 111 n.9). We could also take τό … τό as demonstratives and ἐὸν as the subject of ἔμμϵναι: ‘it is necessary to say this and to think this: that Being is, etc.’; cf. Bernabé (Reference Bernabé, Frank and Giombini2019a) 81 (reading τ<ϵ> νοϵῖν).

48 Along similar lines: (1) Palmer (Reference Palmer2009) 110 (with 113–14 on B6.2); (2) Coxon (Reference Coxon, McKirahan and Schofield2009) 58; Laks and Most (Reference Kraus, Frank and Giombini2016) Parm. D7 (both editions read τ<ϵ> νοϵῖν, but τό could recur for emphasis as the subject of ἔμμϵναι, cf. Laks and Most (Reference Kraus, Frank and Giombini2016) Parm. D7 n.1); (3) Kahn (Reference Kahn1988) 260–61 (reading τ<ϵ> νοϵῖν).

49 For this rendering, see Burnet (Reference Burnet1930) 174; Cornford (Reference Cornford1939) 31; Owen (Reference Owen1960) 94–95; Furth (Reference Furth1968) 119; Ketchum (Reference Ketchum1990) 177; tentatively: Kraus (Reference Kraus1987) 79–80.

50 Kahn (Reference Kahn1988) 260–61, with further detailed criticism; cf. Palmer (Reference Palmer2009) 110; Marcinkowska-Rosół (Reference Marcinkowska-Rosół2010) 97. Marcinkowska-Rosół (Reference Marcinkowska-Rosół2010) 106–13, though, arrives at a similar upshot with the emendation τὸ λέγϵις τὸ νοϵῖς τ’. But there is no warrant for emending the infinitives (and so producing a lectio facilior).

51 For χρή as conveying normative necessity, see Mourelatos (Reference Mourelatos2008) xxxi, 277–78.

52 The goddess makes one other reference to speech in her equally difficult and uncertain remark: οὐ γὰρ ἄνϵυ τοῦ ἐόντος, ἐν ᾧ πϵϕατισμένον ἐστιν, | ϵὑρήσϵις τὸ νοϵῖν (B8.35–36). The most plausible construals that have been proposed are: ‘for not without what-is, in what has been expressed [sc. the foregoing verses], will you find cognizing [alternatively, ‘thinking’ or ‘understanding’]’ (cf. Sedley (Reference Sedley and Long1999) 120); ‘for not without what-is, in that in which cognizing has been expressed [sc. the foregoing verses], will you find cognizing’ (cf. Robbiano (Reference Robbiano2006) 169–70); ‘for not without what-is, depending upon which cognizing has been expressed, will you find cognizing’ (cf. Mourelatos (Reference Mourelatos2008) 170–72; Palmer (Reference Palmer2009) 164 n.40). Plausibly, then, the goddess refers to the preceding verses as an expression of something, quite possibly as an expression of cognizing (πϵϕατισμένον ἐστιν), and she emphasizes the dependence of cognizing upon Being in the context of this expression. Nothing here suggests, however, that what-is is the sole possible object of meaningful speech, contra Cornford (Reference Cornford1939) 34.

53 On B93, see Tor (Reference Tor, Eidinow, Kindt and Osborne2016) with references to further scholarship. Robbiano (Reference Robbiano2006) 125–26 relates Parmenides’ talk of ‘signs’ in B8.2 to the mantic scheme of a divinity who issues signs that require interpretation.

54 Bryan (Reference Bryan2012) 85. The goddess’ signs may indicate the nature of the route or, equally, of the attributes of what-is; Palmer (Reference Palmer2009) 139; cf. Mourelatos (Reference Mourelatos2008) 94–95.

55 See section IV. For the signs as pointers that direct us towards reality without purporting to spell it out themselves, cf. Mackenzie (Reference Mackenzie, de Jonge and Rutten2016) 43 (cf. nn.96, 98 below); Robbiano (Reference Robbiano2018) 39 (on Robbiano (Reference Robbiano2016) and (Reference Robbiano2018), see further sections II and IV).

56 οὐδὲ διαιρϵτόν (B8.22), ἀκίνητον … ἄναρχον ἄπαυστον (B8.26–27), οὐκ ἀτϵλϵύτητον … οὐκ ἐπιδϵές (B8.32–33), ἄσυλον (B8.48), etc. Cf. Austin (Reference Austin1986) 12 (‘the entire elenchus operates within a framework of negative proof’); Sattler (Reference Sattler2020) 93, 108–09. Bernabé observes the predominance of negative characterizations and sees in it a rhetorical strategy to underscore the non-traditional nature of Parmenides’ principle: Bernabé (Reference Bernabé, Frank and Giombini2019a) 100–05; (Reference Bernabé, Frank and Giombini2019b) 247–50.

57 Thus θηλυγϵνής for ‘of the female sex’, Aesch. Supp. 28; cf. Coxon (Reference Coxon, McKirahan and Schofield2009) 315. It is for good reasons that a large majority of editors prefer the better-attested μουνογϵνές to the variant reading οὐλομϵλές, see Tarán (Reference Tarán1965) 88–93; Coxon (Reference Coxon, McKirahan and Schofield2009) 4; Mourelatos (Reference Mourelatos2008) 95 n.3; Palmer (Reference Palmer2009) 382.

58 The metaphysical implications of this predicate are not obvious. Tarán (Reference Tarán1965) 92 takes it to mean that what-is is ‘the only thing of its kind’ or ‘unique’, Palmer (Reference Palmer2009) 140 n.7 that what-is is ‘of a single kind’ or ‘uniform’.

59 I thank Jenny Strauss Clay for discussion of this point. Ferella (Reference Ferella and Santamaría2019) finds in μουνογϵνές the echo of an Orphic line (μοῦνος ἔγϵντο, PDerv. col. 16.6 = Bernabé (Reference Bernabé2004) no. 12.4). This is uncertain, but the echo would anyway further connote a sense of dynamic transformation.

60 Some emendation is needed, since Simplicius’ reading ἠδ’ ἀτέλϵστον (in Phys. 9.30, 78, 145) conflicts with the goddess’ insistence that Being is ‘not incomplete’ (οὐκ ἀτϵλϵύτητον, B8.32; also B8.42–43). οὐδ’ ἀτέλϵστον was first suggested by Brandis (Reference Brandis1813) 109–10. ἠδὲ τέλϵιον: Owen (Reference Owen1960) 102, tentatively favoured by Coxon (Reference Coxon, McKirahan and Schofield2009) 315; cf. also ἠδὲ τϵλϵστόν: Karsten (Reference Karsten1835) 89, followed by Tarán (Reference Tarán1965) 94; Palmer (Reference Palmer2009) 383.

61 She now takes herself to have excluded also that what-is could perish (B8.14, 21). For analyses of B8.6–10, see Warren (Reference Warren2007) 87–93; McKirahan (Reference McKirahan, Curd and Graham2008) 193–96.

62 Parmenides here seems to specify a corollary: the same reasoning that excluded the coming-into-being of one what-is would exclude the coming-into-being of a second (third, fourth, etc.); cf. Coxon (Reference Coxon, McKirahan and Schofield2009) 319–20.

63 On Parmenides’ use of the vocabulary of pistis and its cognates, see Mourelatos (Reference Mourelatos2008) 136–63.

64 For discussion, see Mourelatos (Reference Mourelatos2008) 25–29, 37–40, 115–20, 148–54, 160–61; Austin (Reference Austin1986) 110–13; Robbiano (Reference Robbiano2006) 162–76. It is tempting to consider the various restraining goddesses as different aspects of the same principle; cf. Mourelatos (Reference Mourelatos2008) 160–61 on Constraint-Fate-Justice-Persuasion as representations of the ‘modality of necessity’ determining the identity of what-is, spanning a spectrum from gentle persuasion (B8.12) to brute force.

65 Evans (Reference Evans2021) sees the appeal to Justice at B8.14 as performing a more robust role within the argumentation than is usually thought: Justice is what ensures, crucially, that what-is is reliable and therefore stable (especially pp. 24–33). Evans continues, however, to see this Justice as in reality an immanent aspect of what-is (pp. 30–33) and her shackling as non-literal imagery (p. 3). On his account too, then, one may still wonder about the tension between this imagery itself and the entity in relation to which it is used.

66 Victoria Wohl is currently working on a study in which she notes the variance between the (violent) imagery of bonds and the conception of what-is as self-constituted and sees here one instance of metaphysic’s essential inability to extricate itself from metaphor. For Being as a chained Titan, cf. Cerri (Reference Cerri2018) 229–30, comparing Aeschylus’ Prometheus. Morgan (Reference Morgan, Iribarren and Koning2022) shows how Parmenides appropriates especially Hesiod’s descriptions (Theog. 521–22, 613–23, 652, 659, 717–21) of Titans and Giants who opposed Zeus and were subsequently chained (in some cases in Tartarus), a particularly resonant echo following Parmenides’ appropriations of Hesiod’s eschatological imagery in B1 (on this appropriation, see Burkert (Reference Burkert1969) 8, 11–13; Pellikaan-Engel (Reference Pellikaan-Engel1978) 8–10). On my view, though, Morgan (Reference Morgan, Iribarren and Koning2022) underplays (especially at p. 233) the tension between the binding imagery and the surrounding account of what-is. On binding in Hesiod as a means of controlling specifically deathless threats to cosmic order (such as the Titans), see Clay (Reference Clay, Clay and Vergados2022).

67 I follow Coxon (Reference Coxon, McKirahan and Schofield2009) 327 on ἀκίνητον as indicating a general changelessness that includes the absence of locomotion; cf. B1.29 (ἀτρϵμὲς ἦτορ); for the construal ‘immovable’, see Hutchinson (Reference Hutchinson2020) 207–08. We find no overt argument in B8 for the motionlessness and changelessness of what-is. The interesting attempts to recover an argument in McKirahan (Reference McKirahan, Curd and Graham2008) 205–10 strain the fragments. Melissus (DK30 B7.2, 7) develops such arguments in (at least broadly) Parmenidean terms; see Harriman (Reference Harriman2019) 154–63, 181–93 for discussion.

68 In relation to B8.21 and 27–28, Cherubin (Reference Cherubin2017) 254 observes that the goddess ‘piles on’ the terminology of becoming, perishing and motion; cf. Cherubin (Reference Cherubin2018) 11–12; see also Hutchinson (Reference Hutchinson2020) 192, 207, 253.

69 This syntactical construal of B8.34 follows Kraus (Reference Kraus1987) 77; Palmer (Reference Palmer2009) 164. We may alternatively or in addition take the line to state that cognizing and the cognition that Being is are identical (Cornford (Reference Cornford1939) 34), or that cognizing is identical with that because of which there is cognition, that is, Being (Long (Reference Long1996) 136; Sedley (Reference Sedley and Long1999) 120). On alternative construals of B8.35–36, see n.52 above. On any analysis of B8.34–36, however, νοϵῖν must be used here as a normative success term and in reference to the successful cognition or understanding of what-is. It is elsewhere clear that our minds can fail to grasp what-is (B6.5–6; B16); cf. Mourelatos (Reference Mourelatos2008) 175–76; Calvo (Reference Calvo1977) 251.

70 For this translation of τῷ πάντ’ ὄνομ’ ἔσται (as opposed to the traditional ‘therefore, all things will be a mere name …’, which postulates a ‘mere’ that the Greek does not support), see Kingsley (Reference Kingsley2003) 190–91; Mourelatos (Reference Mourelatos2008) 386–87; cf. Od. 19.409 (τῷ δ’ Ὀδυσϵὺς ὄνομ’ ἔστω); Hymn. Hom. Ven. 198. This translation diminishes the difference in meaning between this text and the alternative reading τῷ πάντ’ ὀνόμασται (‘to it all things will be named’; Woodbury (Reference Woodbury, Anton and Kustas1971); Vlastos (Reference Vlastos and Mourelatos2008); Kraus (Reference Kraus1987) 92–94), which faces philological difficulties (see Mourelatos (Reference Mourelatos2008) 386).

71 The strength and precise nature of the connection announced in (i) between what-is and cognizing will vary according to different syntactical construals of B8.34–36; cf. nn.52, 69 above. Minimally, however, these lines indicate that what-is is a necessary condition for what the goddess here refers to as ‘cognizing’ (or ‘thinking’ or ‘understanding’). It is difficult to know precisely what to make of the γάρ that connects (ib) to (ia). Even if we grant that, in the foregoing lines of Reality (if this is indeed the force of ἐν ᾧ πϵϕατισμένον ἐστιν), cognizing was never separate from or independent of what-is (ib), how would this justify the claim that cognizing is cognizing of what-is (ia)? We should perhaps interpret the γάρ at B8.35 as something like ‘consider how’ and take (ib) to offer only illustrative support for (ia): the fact that, throughout Reality, cognizing was never separate from what-is illustrates (even if it does not prove) that the cognizing of which the goddess speaks here is cognizing of what-is. At any rate, (ii) likely grounds Parmenides’ claim in (i) as a whole, rather than only (ib) but not (ia).

72 On these issues, see section II above.

73 Cf. B8.22–25 (οὐδὲ διαιρϵτόν κ.τ.λ.), 26–31 (ἀκίνητον).

74 ‘Portion’, ‘part’: Il. 10.253; 16.68; ‘division’, ‘distribution’, ‘lot’: Il. 9.318; 15.195; Od. 8.470; Hes. Theog. 413; Hdt. 2.147; ‘lot in life’, ‘fate’: Od. 4.475; 19.592; for the goddess or goddesses, see Il. 24.209; Hes. Theog. 904–06; Aesch. Cho. 306, 910–11; cf. Cherubin (Reference Cherubin2017) 269 n.19. Cherubin (Reference Cherubin2017) 258 also emphasizes the tension between division into shares (μοῖρα) and the indivisible what-is. I cannot see, however, how we could justify from the text her further suggestion here that Moira represents a requisite for inquiry that quite specifically renders inquiry dependent on securing continuous explanatory linkages among multiple things and, therefore, undermines the conception of what-is that the goddess prima facie demonstrates through her own inquiry.

75 Similarly, Jenny Strauss Clay writes (in a study in preparation): ‘the goddess speaks the language of mortals fluently’; cf. Pulpito (Reference Pulpito, Frank and Giombini2019) 193 on the entire poem as ultimately ‘un flujo de onomata’. We must not, then, follow the proposal of Calvo (Reference Calvo1977) that Reality and Opinion represent the opposition of two different kinds of language, even if they do represent different kinds of thinking.

76 See section II.

77 If ‘Cornford’s Fragment’ is authentic, then Parmenides explicitly referred to ‘being’ as the ‘name’ of the whole (τῷ παντὶ ὄνομ’ ϵἶναι, Pl. Tht. 180e1); see Cornford (Reference Cordero and Cordero1935). But Plato himself presents these words only as the sort of thing typical of ‘Melissuses and Parmenideses’ (180e2) and they more likely reflect what he conceives of as a broadly Eleatic approach. Nonetheless, B8.38 does present what-is as the (de facto) referent of names. For τὸ ἐόν as Being’s name, see Kraus (Reference Kraus1987) 64–69, 96. Robbiano (Reference Robbiano2018) 38 infers from the inclusion of ‘being’ and ‘not-being’ in the catalogue of mortal names (B8.39–41) that even the term ‘to be’ cannot describe what-is. It is preferable, however, to read ϵἶναί τϵ καὶ οὐχί in B8.40 as the compound name, ‘both being and not-being’ (note τϵ καί), and not as two isolated names, which would contradict Parmenides’ earlier assertion that not-being is of necessity ‘unconceived, unnamed’ (ἀνόητον ἀνώνυμον, B8.17) and also his portrayal of mortals as confused thinkers who lack a clear notion of ‘being’; see similarly Vlastos (Reference Vlastos and Mourelatos2008) 368 n.4; Furley (Reference Furley, Lee, Mourelatos and Rorty1973) 7 n.23.

78 What Kahn (Reference Kahn1988) 260 calls a use of the verb with ‘ontological force’.

79 De Rijk (Reference Pulpito, Frank and Giombini1983) 49 classifies every occurrence of the verb ‘to be’ in Parmenides as technical (for example, B2.3; 8.16) or non-technical (in addition to B8.54, cf. also B1.11, 27; 6.9; 8.57; 9.3; 16.3–4; 19.1).

80 This is the case whether we think of other things as non-existent illusions or as existing items that display an imperfect mode of being (and so could only be said to be through a compromised and loose use of the term); see section II.

81 πέλϵιν is etymologically connected to an Indo-European family of words signifying motion. The compounds ἀμϕιπέλομαι, ἐπιπέλομαι and πϵριπέλομαι, and the derivatives πολέω and πολϵύω, are all motion verbs, while cognate nominal forms (αἰπόλος, ἱπποπόλος, δικασπόλος, etc.) express some sort of activity. See Chantraine (Reference Cerri1968), s.v. πέλομαι; Beekes (Reference Beekes2009), s.v. πέλομαι. This strikes me as sufficient grounds for allowing that πέλϵιν, especially in the movement-rich context of B6 and in the marked alliterative conjunction with ἰσοπαλές in B8.44–45 (as discussed anon), has a secondary connotation of motion and dynamic change. We need not go so far as to insist that the bare verb πέλω itself still occasionally means ‘to move’ (or similar) by the time of our earliest sources. It is not inconceivable that it could, but most lexicographers are sceptical. Chantraine (Reference Chantraine1968), for example, maintains that we only ever find it in the ‘weakened’ senses ‘se produire, exister, être’. Conversely, Bailly (Reference Bailly1935) s.v. πέλω, 1, lists passages in which he considers πέλω a motion verb. In all of Bailly’s examples it is unnecessary to follow his reading, and in the first three one wonders whether any sense of motion we detect should be credited to the verb in conjunction with a preposition rather than to the verb alone: Il. 3.3 (πέλϵι οὐρανόθι πρό); Od. 13.59–60 (ἔλθῃ … ἐπ᾽ ἀνθρώποισι πέλονται); Od. 15.407–08 (ἐπὶ … πέλϵται δϵιλοῖσι βροτοῖσιν); Od. 19.192 (‘but now the tenth or eleventh dawn came/took place (πέλϵν)’; cf. πϵριπλομένων ἐνιαυτῶν, Od. 1.16). At any rate, the sense of becoming is clear in these passages and not infrequently elsewhere (Il. 13.103, 632; Od. 1.393). Autenrieth (Reference Autenrieth1891) s.v. πέλω oversimplifies when he remarks: ‘perhaps originally containing some idea of motion … but in Homer simply to be’.

82 I noncommittally follow the reading πέλοι τὸ ἐόν (Laks and Most (Reference Kraus, Frank and Giombini2016) Parm. D8.24) over πέλοιτο ἐόν (Coxon (Reference Coxon, McKirahan and Schofield2009) ad loc.).

83 Mourelatos (Reference Mourelatos2008) 123–24 with n.24. For words in the root παλ- with the sense of striving or fighting, cf. πάλη, παλαίω, πάλαισμα, παλαιστής, etc.; see Chantraine (Reference Cerri1968), s.v. παλαίω.

84 πέλϵιν also occurs in Reality at B8.11 (ἢ πάμπαν πϵλέναι χρϵών ἐστιν ἢ οὐχί).

85 See Sedley (Reference Sedley and Long1999) 121–22; for Being as spatially extended, see also Schofield (Reference Schofield1970) 131–34.

86 Mourelatos (Reference Mourelatos2008) 123–28.

87 That Parmenides should have been exercised by these concerns is not surprising from a historical perspective. We find different responses to comparable preoccupations with the limitations, partiality and shiftiness of human language and human names in, for example, Hesiod (see Vergados Reference Vergados2020), Pherecydes (Granger (Reference Granger2007) 144–47) and Heraclitus (Kirk (Reference Kirk1962) 116–22; Graeser (Reference Graeser1977b) 365–66; Kahn (Reference Kahn1979) 270–71; Dilcher (Reference Dilcher1995) 124–25).

88 And, in the special case of the sphere analogy, by comparing what-is to an item of everyday sensory experience: the bulk of a ball.

89 This is the attested meaning of the word ἀδαής (for example, Pind. Pae. 4.27) and would have been prominent for a contemporary audience. It fits with Theophrastus’ testimony regarding the cognitive superiority of the other element (A46), cf. Coxon (Reference Coxon, McKirahan and Schofield2009) 348; Tor (Reference Tor2017) 249 with n.69. In context, it is tempting to allow ‘without light’ (vel sim.) as a further possible sense, but I know of no parallels (cf. DK ad loc., who hypothesize a connection with δάος, ‘torch’: ‘lichtlose … nur hier in dieser Bedeutung (?)’). In Tor (Reference Tor2017) 185–86 with n.55, I rendered ἀδαῆ ‘dark’ and noted that the term also indicates ignorance, but I would now translate it as ‘unknowing’ or ‘unintelligent’, while allowing darkness as a possible further connotation.

90 For the echoes of Xenophanes’ Greatest God in Parmenides, see Bryan (Reference Bryan2012) 97–100. For negative theological characterizations in Xenophanes, see B1.21–24; 11–12; 14–16; 18; 23; 25–26.

91 I come close here to the view of Morgan (Reference Morgan2000) 81–87, that Parmenides’ mythological imagery is emblematic of language’s general inability to express reality. Morgan, however, relies on some general assumptions about philosophical hostility to myth (pp. 47, 84; cf. 16–17, 34–35, 290–91) and does not pursue the particular tensions between Reality’s imagery and doctrine explored above. Since Morgan assumes that, for Parmenides, ‘only being exists’ (p. 82), she takes it, in a way reminiscent of Plato’s Eleatic Stranger, that any mention of anything other than Being already violates Reality’s ontology (especially pp. 80–84).

92 A note of caution is in order. By recognizing that we should not interpret literally some or all of what we are inclined to describe as mythological imagery in Parmenides, we need not thereby exclude religious import in such imagery or, for example, rule out that Parmenides makes real claims for divine revelation. On this point, cf. Gernet (Reference Gernet, Gernet, Hamilton and Nagy1981) 354; Tor (Reference Tor2017) 162; Bernabé (Reference Bernabé, Frank and Giombini2019a) 68–69.

93 For the denial that B8 offers a description of what-is, see Mason (Reference Mason1988); Robbiano (Reference Robbiano2016) 275–82; (Reference Robbiano2018). Robbiano interprets being as ‘the fact of being’ rather than an object or entity. Whatever view we hold of the subjectless ‘is’ in B2, however, by B8 we encounter ‘what-is’ or ‘being’ ((τὸ) ἐόν) as a grammatical subject to which the goddess ascribes properties. Even if, as Robbiano (Reference Robbiano2016) 280–81 emphasizes, B8 is preoccupied with rejecting would-be ascriptions of certain predicates to what-is (‘generated’, etc.), the goddess shows no hesitation about consequently affirming for what-is the contradictories of those predicates (‘not-generated’). Robbiano’s interpretation could work in principle, then, only if we could coherently construe ‘the fact of being’ as the bearer of all those properties (ungenerated, imperishable, all alike, indivisible, unmoving, spherical or spherical-like, etc.). The textual strain of her denial that B8 offers a description of what-is is visible when, at one juncture, Robbiano (Reference Robbiano2016) 288, cf. 298, seems conversely to pursue just this route and to recognize the goddess’ predications, writing in passing that the fact of being ‘is without birth and death, continuous and without lack, as becomes clear in B8’. I leave aside Robbiano’s other fascinating central thesis, that what-is is identical with our experience and awareness of it and is not ‘distinct from a subject observing it’ or ‘searching’ for it (Robbiano (Reference Robbiano2016) 263, 270, 291 and passim). I note only that this further claim faces the difficulty that some things are always true of what-is (for example, it does not move or change) but sometimes false of subjects who search for it (such as the kouros or his mind).

94 See further Barrett (Reference Barrett2004) 279–87; Gianvittorio (Reference Gianvittorio2013) 17–19; Macé (Reference Macé and Horky2019) 49–51.

95 As discussed in section III: text with nn.53–55. See there also on the possible exception of the term (or ‘name’?) τὸ ἐόν: text with n.77. Although mortals too employ their own ‘signs’ in their cosmology, these are differentiated from the goddess’ signs in Reality. Most pertinently, the cosmological signs of the mortals are always subordinated to those committal ‘names’ that they trust unreservedly: … ὀνομάζϵιν … καὶ σήματ’ ἔθϵντο … (B8.53–55), ὄνομ’ … ἐπίσημον (B19.3). Furthermore, while the goddess’ signs are presented as waiting there to be discovered on the road of what-is (ταύτῃ δ᾽ ἐπὶ σήματ’ ἔασι, B8.2), Parmenides emphasizes the conventional status of mortal names and their attendant signs: κατέθϵντο (B8.38–39, 53–55), κατέθϵντ’ ἐπίσημον (B19.3); on this point, see Coxon (Reference Coxon, McKirahan and Schofield2009) 334, 343–44, 387 (on ἐπίσημον as ‘a metaphor from coinage’); cf. Nussbaum (Reference Nussbaum1979) 73–75; Kraus (Reference Kraus1987) 91; Mansfeld (Reference Mansfeld2021) 211–14. See further Macé (Reference Macé and Horky2019) 49–52, 56–57 on the role of human names and signs in constituting Opinion’s ‘deceptive arrangement (κόσμον) of words’ (B8.52).

96 So Owen (Reference Owen1960) 100; (Reference Owen1966) 321–22, repurposing the image of the ladder from Sextus (Math. 8.481) and Wittgenstein (Tractatus 6.54); followed by, for example, Graeser (Reference Graeser1977b) 365; Mackenzie (Reference Mackenzie, de Jonge and Rutten2016) 43–44. Owen had in mind Parmenides’ use of negations and of temporal and spatial distinctions (relying on interpretive assumptions criticized in section II above).

97 Mourelatos (Reference Mourelatos2008) 161 underscores that the shackling goddesses have the status of figurative imagery and are not ‘an element of the ontology’; cf. Bryan (Reference Bryan2020b) 88–90.

98 For different elaborations of the view that, for Parmenides, language has only heuristic value in the context of ontological inquiry, see Owen (Reference Owen1960) 100; Mackenzie (Reference Mackenzie, de Jonge and Rutten2016) 43; (Reference Mackenzie2021) 69–70; Robbiano (Reference Robbiano2016) 275–82; (Reference Robbiano2018); Sattler (Reference Sattler2020) 108–09.

99 On the ineffability of the One in Plotinus and his consequent discursive strategies, see Banner (Reference Banner2018); Coope (Reference Coope2020) 78–92.

References

Austin, S. (1986) Parmenides: Being, Bounds, and Logic (New Haven and London)Google Scholar
Autenrieth, G. (1891) A Homeric Dictionary for Schools and Colleges (New York)Google Scholar
Bailly, A. (1935) Dictionnaire grec–français (Paris)Google Scholar
Banner, N. (2018) Philosophic Silence and the ‘One’ in Plotinus (Cambridge)Google Scholar
Barrett, J. (2004) ‘Struggling with Parmenides’, AncPhil 24, 267–91Google Scholar
Beekes, R. (2009) Etymological Dictionary of Greek (Leiden and Boston)Google Scholar
Bernabé, A. (2004) Poetae Epici Graeci: Testimonia et Fragmenta. Pars II. Orphicorum et Orphicis Similium Testimonia et Fragmenta. Fasciculus 1 (Munich and Leipzig)Google Scholar
Bernabé, A. (2019a) ‘Parménides: entre lingüística, literatura y filosofía’, in Frank, B.B. and Giombini, S. (eds), Parmenide: tra linguistica, letteratura e filosofia—Parménides: entre lingüística, literatura y filosofía (Baden-Baden) 49118 Google Scholar
Bernabé, A. (2019b) ‘Respuestas’, in Frank, B.B. and Giombini, S. (eds), Parmenide: tra linguistica, letteratura e filosofia—Parménides: entre lingüística, literatura y filosofía (Baden-Baden) 221–50Google Scholar
Brandis, C.A. (1813) Commentationum Eleaticarum Pars Prima (Altona)Google Scholar
Brémond, M. (2017) Lectures de Mélissos. Édition, traduction et interprétation des témoignages sur Mélissos de Samos (Berlin and Boston)Google Scholar
Brown, L. (1986) ‘Being in the Sophist: a syntactical enquiry’, OSAPh 4, 4970 Google Scholar
Brown, L. (1994) ‘The verb “to be” in Greek philosophy: some remarks’, in Everson, S. (ed.), Companions to Ancient Thought, Vol. III: Language (Cambridge) 212–36Google Scholar
Bryan, J. (2012) Likeness and Likelihood in the Presocratics and Plato (Cambridge)Google Scholar
Bryan, J. (2020a) ‘The pursuit of Parmenidean clarity’, Rhizomata 8, 218–38Google Scholar
Bryan, J. (2020b) ‘The non-divinity of Parmenides’ what-is’, Anais de Filosofia Clássica 27, 7195 Google Scholar
Burkert, W. (1969) ‘Das Proömium des Parmenides und die Katabasis des Pythagoras’, Phronesis 14, 130 Google Scholar
Burnet, J. (1930) Early Greek Philosophy (4th edition) (London)Google Scholar
Calvo, T. (1977) ʻTruth and doxa in Parmenides’, AGPh 59, 2460 Google Scholar
Castagnoli, L. (2010) Ancient Self-Refutation: The Logic and History of the Self-Refutation Argument from Democritus to Augustine (Cambridge)Google Scholar
Cerri, G. (2018) Parmenide di Elea. Poema sulla natura (8th edition) (Milan)Google Scholar
Chantraine, P. (1968) Dictionnaire étymologique de la langue grecque (Paris)Google Scholar
Cherubin, R. (2017) ‘Mortals lay down trusting to be true’, Epoché 21, 251–71Google Scholar
Cherubin, R. (2018) ‘Parmenides, liars and mortal incompleteness’, Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 33, 121 Google Scholar
Clay, J.S. (2022) ‘Ties that bind: verbal fetters and ring composition in Hesiod’s Theogony ’, in Clay, J.S. and Vergados, A. (eds), Teaching through Images: Imagery in Greco-Roman Didactic Poetry (Mnemosyne Supplement 450) (Leiden and Boston) 2338 Google Scholar
Cole, T. (1983) ‘Archaic truth’, QUCC 13, 728 Google Scholar
Coope, U. (2020) Freedom and Responsibility in Neoplatonist Thought (Oxford)Google Scholar
Cordero, N.-L. (2011) ‘Parmenidean “Physics” is not part of what Parmenides calls δόξα’, in Cordero, N.-L. (ed.), Parmenides, Venerable and Awesome (Las Vegas) 95113 Google Scholar
Cornford, F.M. (1935) ‘A new fragment of Parmenides’, CR 49, 122–23Google Scholar
Cornford, F.M. (1939) Plato and Parmenides (London)Google Scholar
Coxon, A.H. (2009) The Fragments of Parmenides: Revised and Expanded Edition (ed. with new translations McKirahan, R., preface Schofield, M.) (Las Vegas)Google Scholar
Curd, P.K. (1998) The Legacy of Parmenides: Eleatic Monism and Later Presocratic Thought (Princeton)Google Scholar
Curd, P.K. (2015) ‘Thinking, supposing, and physis in Parmenides’, EPlaton 12 https://journals.openedition.org/etudesplatoniciennes/741 Google Scholar
de Rijk, L.M. (1983) ‘Did Parmenides reject the sensible world?’, in Gerson, L.P. (ed.), Graceful Reason (Toronto) 2953 Google Scholar
Di Iulio, E. (2021) ‘Parmenides on “naming” and “meaning”: a disjunctivist reading of the poem’, Philosophy 96, 205–27Google Scholar
Dilcher, R. (1995) Studies in Heraclitus (Hildesheim)Google Scholar
Evans, M. (2021) ‘The work of Justice in Parmenides B 8’, OSAPh 60, 143 Google Scholar
Ferella, C. (2019) ‘Ζϵὺς μοῦνος and Parmenides’ what-is ’, in Santamaría, M.A. (ed.), The Derveni Papyrus: Unearthing Ancient Mysteries (Leiden and Boston) 6574 Google Scholar
Ferro, F. (2020) ‘L’ἐόν e la sua manifestazione cosmica nel Poema di Parmenide’, in Galgano, N.S., Giombini, S. and Marcacci, F. (eds), Verso la filosofia: Nuove prospettive su Parmenide, Zenone e Melisso (Baden-Baden) 209–24Google Scholar
Folit-Weinberg, B. (2022) Homer, Parmenides, and the Road to Demonstration (Cambridge)Google Scholar
Furley, D.J. (1973) ‘Notes on Parmenides’, in Lee, E.N., Mourelatos, A.P.D. and Rorty, R.M. (eds), Exegesis and Argument: Studies in Greek Philosophy Presented to Gregory Vlastos (Assen) 115 Google Scholar
Furth, M. (1968) ‘Elements of Eleatic ontology’, JHPh 6.2, 111–32Google Scholar
Gallop, D. (1984) Parmenides of Elea (Toronto)Google Scholar
Gernet, L. (1981) ‘The origins of Greek philosophy’, in Gernet, L., The Anthropology of Ancient Greece (tr. Hamilton, J. and Nagy, B.) (Baltimore) 352–64Google Scholar
Gianvittorio, L. (2013) ‘Sprechen und Verstehen bei Heraklit und Parmenides’, Mnemosyne 66, 129 Google Scholar
Graeser, A. (1977a) ‘Parmenides über Sagen und Denken’, MH 34, 145–55Google Scholar
Graeser, A. (1977b) ‘On language, thought, and reality in ancient Greek philosophy’, Dialectica 31, 359–88Google Scholar
Graham, D.W. (2010) The Texts of Early Greek Philosophy: The Complete Fragments and Selected Testimonies of the Major Presocratics 1 (Cambridge)Google Scholar
Granger, H. (2007) ‘The theologian Pherecydes of Syros and the early days of natural philosophy’, HSPh 103, 135–63Google Scholar
Harriman, B. (2019) Melissus and Eleatic Monism (Cambridge)Google Scholar
Hutchinson, G.O. (2020) Motion in Classical Literature: Homer, Parmenides, Sophocles, Ovid, Seneca, Tacitus, Art (Oxford)Google Scholar
Johansen, T.K. (2016) ‘Parmenides’ likely story’, OSAPh 50, 129 Google Scholar
Kahn, C.H. (1969) ‘The thesis of Parmenides’, RMeta 22, 700–24Google Scholar
Kahn, C.H. (1979) The Art and Thought of Heraclitus (Cambridge)Google Scholar
Kahn, C.H. (1988) ‘Being in Parmenides and Plato’, PP 43, 237–61Google Scholar
Karsten, S. (1835) Parmenidis Eleatae Carminis Reliquiae (Amsterdam)Google Scholar
Ketchum, R.J. (1990) ‘Parmenides on what there is’, CJPh 20, 16790 Google Scholar
Kingsley, P. (2003) Reality (Inverness CA)Google Scholar
Kirk, G.S. (1962) Heraclitus: The Cosmic Fragments (Cambridge)Google Scholar
Kraus, M. (1987) Name und Sache: Ein Problem im frühgriechischen Denken (Amsterdam)Google Scholar
Kraus, M. (2019) ‘Commento ad Alberto Bernabé, Parménides a través del prisma de la lingüística ’, in Frank, B.B. and Giombini, S. (eds), Parmenide: tra linguistica, letteratura e filosofia—Parménides: entre lingüística, literatura y filosofía (Baden-Baden) 181–88Google Scholar
Laks, A. and Most, G.W. (eds and trans) (2016) Early Greek Philosophy (9 vols) (Cambridge MA)Google Scholar
Lampe, K. (2020) ‘The logos of ethics in Gorgias’ Palamedes, On What Is Not, and Helen ’, in Wolfsdorf, D. (ed.), Early Greek Ethics (Oxford) 110–31Google Scholar
Long, A.A. (1996) ‘Parmenides on thinking being’, Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 12, 125–62Google Scholar
Macé, A. (2019) ‘Ordering the universe in speech: kosmos and diakosmos in Parmenides’ poem’, in Horky, P.S. (ed.), Cosmos in the Ancient World (Cambridge) 4261 Google Scholar
Mackenzie, M.M. (1982) ‘Parmenides’ dilemma’, Phronesis 27, 112 Google Scholar
Mackenzie, T. (2016) ‘Language and learning with the Presocratics: Xenophanes and Parmenides as educators and linguists’, in de Jonge, C. and Rutten, G.J. (eds), The History of Linguistics in the Context of Education (Beiträge zur Geschichte der Sprachwissenschaft 26.1) (Münster) 2548 Google Scholar
Mackenzie, T. (2021) Poetry and Poetics in the Presocratic Philosophers: Reading Xenophanes, Parmenides and Empedocles as Literature (Cambridge)Google Scholar
Mansfeld, J. (1964) Die Offenbarung des Parmenides und die Menschliche Welt (Assen)Google Scholar
Mansfeld, J. (1999) ‘Parménide et Héraclite avaient-ils une théorie de la perception?’, Phronesis 44, 326–46Google Scholar
Mansfeld, J. (2016) ‘Melissus between Miletus and Elea’, in Pulpito, M. (ed.), Eleatica 2012: Melissus between Miletus and Elea (Sankt-Augustin) 71112 Google Scholar
Mansfeld, J. (2019) ‘“Il faut que vous soyez instruits de toutes choses …”’, EPlaton 15 https://journals.openedition.org/etudesplatoniciennes/1458 Google Scholar
Mansfeld, J. (2021) ‘An early Greek epic: narrative structure in Parmenides’ poem and the relation between its main parts’, Mnemosyne 74, 200–37Google Scholar
Marcinkowska-Rosół, M. (2010) Die Konzeption des ‘noein’ bei Parmenides von Elea (Berlin and New York)Google Scholar
Mason, R. (1988) ‘Parmenides and language’, AncPhil 8, 149–66Google Scholar
McCabe, M.M. (2000) Plato and His Predecessors: The Dramatisation of Reason (Cambridge)10.1017/CBO9780511552601CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McKirahan, R.D. (2008) ‘Signs and arguments in Parmenides B8’, in Curd, P.K. and Graham, D.W. (eds), The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy (Oxford) 189229 Google Scholar
Morgan, K. (2000) Myth and Philosophy from the Presocratics to Plato (Cambridge)Google Scholar
Morgan, K. (2022) ‘Parmenides and the language of constraint’, in Iribarren, L. and Koning, H.H. (eds), Hesiod and the Beginnings of Greek Philosophy (Mnemosyne Supplement 455) (Leiden and Boston), 221–38.Google Scholar
Mourelatos, A.P.D. (1979) ‘Some alternatives in interpreting Parmenides’, The Monist 62, 314 Google Scholar
Mourelatos, A.P.D. (2008) The Route of Parmenides: Revised and Expanded Edition (Las Vegas)Google Scholar
Nehamas, A. (2002) ‘Parmenidean being/Heraclitean fire’, in Caston, V. and Graham, D.W. (eds), Presocratic Philosophy: Essays in Honour of Alexander Mourelatos (Aldershot) 4564 Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M.C. (1979) ‘Eleatic conventionalism and Philolaus on the conditions of thought’, HSPh 83, 63108 Google Scholar
Owen, G.E.L. (1960) ‘Eleatic questions’, CQ 10, 84102 Google Scholar
Owen, G.E.L. (1966) ‘Plato and Parmenides on the timeless present’, The Monist 50, 317–40Google Scholar
Owens, J. (1975) ‘Naming in Parmenides’, in Mansfeld, J. and de Rijk, L.M. (eds), Kephalaion: Studies in Greek Philosophy and Its Continuation (Assen) 1625 Google Scholar
Palmer, J.A. (1999) Plato’s Reception of Parmenides (Oxford)Google Scholar
Palmer, J.A. (2009) Parmenides and Presocratic Philosophy (Oxford)Google Scholar
Pellikaan-Engel, M.E. (1978) Hesiod and Parmenides: A New View on Their Cosmologies and on Parmenides’ Proem (Amsterdam)Google Scholar
Pulpito, M. (2019) ‘El “giro lingüístico” de Parménides’, in Frank, B.B. and Giombini, S. (eds), Parmenide: tra linguistica, letteratura e filosofia—Parménides: entre lingüística, literatura y filosofía (Baden-Baden) 189201 Google Scholar
Robbiano, C. (2006) Becoming Being: On Parmenides’ Transformative Philosophy (Sankt Augustin)Google Scholar
Robbiano, C. (2016) ‘ Being is not an object: an interpretation of Parmenides fragment DK B2 and a reflection on assumptions’, AncPhil 36, 263301 Google Scholar
Robbiano, C. (2018) ‘Can words carve a jointless reality? Parmenides and Śaṅkara’, Journal of World Philosophies 3, 3143 Google Scholar
Rossetti, L. (2020) ‘Verso la filosofia. Nuove prospettive su Parmenide, Zenone e Melisso’, in Galgano, N.S., Giombini, S. and Marcacci, F. (eds), Verso la filosofia: Nuove prospettive su Parmenide, Zenone e Melisso (Baden-Baden) 51167 Google Scholar
Sanders, K.R. (2002) ‘Much ado about “nothing”: μηδέν and τὸ μὴ ἐόν in Parmenides’, Apeiron 35, 87104 Google Scholar
Sattler, B.M. (2020) The Concept of Motion in Ancient Greek Thought (Cambridge)Google Scholar
Schofield, M. (1970) ‘Did Parmenides discover eternity?’, AGPh 52, 113–35Google Scholar
Sedley, D.N. (1999) ‘Parmenides and Melissus’, in Long, A.A. (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Early Greek Philosophy (Cambridge) 113–33Google Scholar
Sisko, J.E. and Weiss, Y. (2015) ‘A fourth alternative in interpreting Parmenides’, Phronesis 60, 4059 Google Scholar
Škiljan, D. (1998) ‘La pensée linguistique grecque avant Socrate’, CFS 51, 1128 Google Scholar
Svenbro, J. (1993) Phrasikleia: An Anthropology of Reading in Ancient Greece (tr. Lloyd, J.) (Ithaca and London)Google Scholar
Tarán, L. (1965) Parmenides: A Text with Translation, Commentary, and Critical Essays (Princeton)Google Scholar
Thanassas, P. (2011) ‘Parmenidean dualisms’, in Cordero, N.-L. (ed.), Parmenides, Venerable and Awesome (Las Vegas) 289308 Google Scholar
Tor, S. (2016) ‘Heraclitus on Apollo’s signs and his own: contemplating oracles and philosophical inquiry’, in Eidinow, E., Kindt, J. and Osborne, R. (eds), Theologies of Ancient Greek Religion (Cambridge) 89116 Google Scholar
Tor, S. (2017) Mortal and Divine in Early Greek Epistemology: A Study of Hesiod, Xenophanes and Parmenides (Cambridge)Google Scholar
Vergados, A. (2020) Hesiod’s Verbal Craft: Studies in Hesiod’s Conception of Language and Its Ancient Reception (Oxford)Google Scholar
Vlastos, G. (2008) ‘“Names” of being in Parmenides’, in Mourelatos, A.P.D. (ed.), The Route of Parmenides: Revised and Expanded Edition (Las Vegas) 367–88Google Scholar
Warren, J. (2007) Presocratics (Stocksfield)Google Scholar
Wedin, M.V. (2014) Parmenides’ Grand Deduction (Oxford)Google Scholar
Weiss, Y. (2018) ‘Commentary on Cherubin’, Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 33, 2226 Google Scholar
Woodbury, L. (1971) ‘Parmenides on names’, in Anton, J.P. and Kustas, G.L. (eds), Essays in Ancient Greek Philosophy 1 (Albany NY) 145–62Google Scholar
Woodbury, L. (1986) ‘Parmenides on naming by mortal men: fr. B8.53–56’, AncPhil 6, 113 Google Scholar