Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-x24gv Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-31T21:33:12.031Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Unjust equal relations

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 May 2024

Andreas Bengtson*
Affiliation:
CEPDISC, Department of Political Science, Aarhus University, Bartholins Allé 7, DK – 8000 Aarhus C, Denmark
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

According to relational egalitarianism, justice requires equal relations. In this paper, I ask the question: can equal relations be unjust according to relational egalitarianism? I argue that while on some conceptions of relational egalitarianism, equal relations cannot be unjust, there are conceptions in which equal relations can be unjust. Surprisingly, whether equal relations can be unjust cuts across the distinction between responsibility-sensitive and non-responsibility-sensitive conceptions of relational egalitarianism. I then show what follows if one accepts a conception in which equal relations can be unjust, including why it provides a reason to grant some people less political power than others.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press

1. Introduction

Suppose that Sexist treats Woman in a sexist manner. According to relational egalitarianism, arguably the most prominent theory of justice in recent years,Footnote 1 this is unjust. Justice requires equal relations. And Sexist fails to relate to Woman as their equal. But if justice requires equal relations, does that mean that equal relations can never be unjust according to relational egalitarianism?Footnote 2 It seems that the answer is yes. After all, if a relation is unequal, and justice requires equal relations, then it straightforwardly follows that the relation is unjust.

I want to show that this is only partly true. It is partly true in the sense that there are relational egalitarianisms according to which equal relations cannot be unjust. But there are other relational egalitarianisms according to which equal relations can be unjust. When I say ‘relational egalitarianisms’, this is to emphasize that relational egalitarianism is a large family of theories that differ along many different dimensions. I will distinguish between two conceptions of relational egalitarianism that take responsibility into account, and two that do not. Now, one might suspect that it is responsibility that makes an important difference here. If people must relate to each other in accordance with their exercise of responsibility,Footnote 3 this may imply that equal relations can be unjust. If Prudent and Lazy relate as equals, this may be unjust. It might, indeed, as I will argue. But, interestingly, I will also argue that whether equal relations can be unjust is not simply a matter of whether we take responsibility into account. Equal relations can be unjust according to a non-responsibility-sensitive conception of relational egalitarianism. And, to make things even more complicated, I will argue that there is a responsibility-sensitive conception of relational egalitarianism in which equal relations cannot be unjust. In short: the question of whether equal relations can be unjust according to relational egalitarianism is complex and intriguing. But it is also highly important. Whether one answers the question affirmatively or not makes a difference to how much political power individuals should have, as I will show. Indeed, if equal relations can be unjust, we may, for relational egalitarian reasons, have to deviate from a ‘one person, one vote’ scheme due to the importance of the political domain for how we relate to each other. This is surprising considering that relational egalitarians argue for the importance of equal political power (see e.g. Anderson Reference Anderson1999; Kolodny Reference Kolodny2014; Viehoff Reference Viehoff2014; Peña-Rangel Reference Peña-Rangel2022).

Thus, I will ask two questions:

  1. (1) Can equal relations be unjust according to relational egalitarianism?

and

  1. (2) If equal relations can be unjust, how does this, implications-wise, affect relational egalitarianism as a theory of justice?

In sections 2 and 3, I answer the first question affirmatively: there are conceptions of relational egalitarianism according to which equal relations can be unjust. In section 4, I answer the second question. I show that: it affects how much political power people should have; it means that there may be situations in which relational egalitarian justice requires what is bad for individuals (but that this is also the case even if equal relations cannot be unjust); and it means that relational egalitarianism is similar to luck egalitarianism, the most prominent distributive theory of justice, in that equality may be unjust. Section 5 concludes.

Before I move on, I need to make a quick clarification in relation to the first question, i.e. the question of whether equal relations can be unjust according to relational egalitarianism. On a pluralist view according to which relational equality is only one of the demands of justice, egalitarian relationships can be straightforwardly unjust if they violate some other, non-relational demand of justice (demands that do not have to do with how people relate to each other). The question which I am asking is not whether egalitarian relationships may be objectionable for such non-relational reasons. I am asking whether egalitarian relationships can be unjust on relational grounds.Footnote 4 I will return to this point later.

2. Non-responsibility-sensitive Conceptions of Relational Egalitarianism

Relational egalitarianism is, as mentioned, a large family of theories that differ along many different dimensions, including whether (un)equal relations are personally or impersonally (dis)valuable.Footnote 5 Relevant to our purposes, Lippert-Rasmussen distinguishes between a responsibility-sensitive and a non-responsibility sensitive conception of relational egalitarianism:

Outcome relational egalitarianism: A situation is just only if everyone relates to one another as equals.

Luck relational egalitarianism: A situation is just only if no one relates to others as (superiors/) inferiors through no responsibility of their own (Lippert-Rasmussen Reference Lippert-Rasmussen2018: 7).

In investigating our question – whether equal relations can be unjust according to relational egalitarianism – let us start with outcome relational egalitarianism. Usually, relational egalitarians argue that those with equal moral standing must relate as equals. To exemplify, Lippert-Rasmussen (Reference Lippert-Rasmussen2018: 170) says that ‘as a matter of fact, we are one another’s moral equals and in relating as equals we honour that fact, and this is what grounds the ideal of relational egalitarianism’ (see also Anderson Reference Anderson1999; Schemmel Reference Schemmel2012, Reference Schemmel2021). This expresses the following outcome, or non-responsibility-sensitive, view:

Non-responsibility-sensitive Moral Relational Egalitarianism: A situation is just only if moral equals relate as moral equals.Footnote 6

According to this view, justice requires that people who are moral equals also relate as moral equals. To relate as moral equals has at least two components: agency and interests. If two people are to relate as moral equals, they must take each other’s interests and autonomy to be equally important at a fundamental level (Anderson Reference Anderson1999; Scheffler Reference Scheffler, Fourie, Schuppert and Walliman-Helmer2015; Hojlund Reference Hojlund2022: 57–58). When Sexist treats Woman in a sexist manner, they fail to relate as moral equals because Sexist thereby treats Woman’s agency and interests as if they, at a fundamental level, are less important than their own agency and interests.Footnote 7 This relation would be unjust according to non-responsibility-sensitive moral relational egalitarianism.

But moral standing is not the only dimension in which relational egalitarians believe that moral equals must relate as equals. They also argue that moral equals must relate as social equals. To exemplify, Anderson (Reference Anderson1999: 313) says that ‘[Relational] Egalitarians base claims to social and political equality on the fact of universal moral equality’. Similarly, Kolodny (Reference Kolodny2014: 300) says, ‘Insofar as we are to have ongoing social relations with other moral equals, we have reason to relate to them as social equals – that is, in a way that deliberately avoids whatever asymmetries in power, authority and consideration would constitute relations of social superiority and inferiority, motivated by a concern to avoid these relations at such’. Finally, Viehoff (Reference Viehoff, Sobel, Vallentyne and Wall2019: 18) says, ‘If we are all moral equals, matter equally, etc., then social status hierarchy is objectionable because it treats us as if we were not’.

Whereas moral standing has to do with interests and wills in a fundamental sense, social standing is different.Footnote 8 I follow Kolodny (Reference Kolodny2014: 295–296) in taking social standing to consist of three components: power, de facto authority and consideration.Footnote 9 He understands power in a wide sense to include both formal and informal power.Footnote 10 For instance, adults have more formal power than children in having the right to vote. In this sense, adults have a superior social standing to children. De facto authority has to do with the degree to which one’s commands or requests are generally complied with. That, in the relationship between parent and child, the parent’s requests are generally complied with by the child, but not vice versa, means that the parent has more de facto authority than the child – and that they, in this sense, relate as social unequals. The final dimension, consideration, has to do with the extent to which one has attributes – such as race, lineage, wealth – that attract consideration from others. In a white supremacist society, a white person attracts greater consideration on behalf of their race than a black person. In this sense, the white person stands as a social superior to the black person. These three dimensions can be satisfied to different degrees. The larger the differences in power, de facto authority and consideration, the larger the inequality in the social relation. If there are no differences in power, de facto authority and consideration between Adam and Bert, they relate as social equals. As I said, I will assume this understanding of what it takes to relate as social equals for now. I return to this issue in section 3.

Thus, moral equals must not only relate as moral equals; they must also relate as social equals, according to many relational egalitarians. We can add this to the above view:

Non-responsibility-sensitive Relational Egalitarianism: A situation is just only if moral equals relate as moral and social equals.

Assuming this view, it is clear that equal relations between moral equals are not unjust. However, this view does not tell us how moral unequals should relate to each other. It only tells us how moral equals should relate to each other. One option with regard to moral unequals would be the following:

Broad Non-responsibility-sensitive Relational Egalitarianism: A situation is just only if moral equals relate as moral and social equals and moral unequals relate as moral and social equals.Footnote 11

This view adds to non-responsibility-sensitive relational egalitarianism that moral unequals must also relate as moral and social equals. Why might relational egalitarians want to say that moral unequals should also relate as equals? One reason might be that the reasons for why it is good that moral equals relate as equals also entail that it is good that moral unequals relate as equals. For instance, some relational egalitarians argue that egalitarian relationships are impersonally valuable. O’Neill (Reference O’Neill2008: 130) has most prominently put forward this argument, saying, ‘the existence of these kinds of social relations [egalitarian social relations] should itself be seen as intrinsically valuable, independent of the positive effects that such relations may have for individual welfare’. Even if, in a racist society, an inegalitarian relationship between a black person and a white person may be better for the parties, an egalitarian relationship between them would still be impersonally valuable. Similarly, in a sexist society, an egalitarian marriage would be impersonally valuable even if, for the parties, an inegalitarian relationship would be better, for example because they would thereby not face social sanctions qua not living up to the social norms in society.

If one believes that there is impersonal value in egalitarian relationships between moral equals, it seems natural to also believe that there is impersonal (dis)value in (in)egalitarian relationships between moral unequals (Bengtson and Lippert-Rasmussen Reference Bengtson and Lippert-Rasmussen2023: 403–404).Footnote 12 After all, one does not have to say that there is as much impersonal value in the latter kind of relationship as in the former. It is perfectly consistent to say that even though egalitarian relationships between moral unequals do not have as much impersonal value as egalitarian relationships between moral equals, they are still impersonally valuable. So this would be one reason why relational egalitarians might want to say that moral unequals should also relate as moral and social equals.

According to broad non-responsibility-sensitive relational egalitarianism, there can be no unjust equal moral or social relations. Since justice according to this view requires both that moral equals and moral unequals relate as moral and social equals, there are no beings left – at least not beings with moral standing – between whom an equal relation may be unjust. Only unequal relations can be unjust. Indeed, any unequal moral or social relation between persons (and persons and animals, for that matter)Footnote 13 would in fact be unjust according to this view.

Now, one might argue against broad non-responsibility-sensitive relational egalitarianism that it is implausible that moral unequals should relate as social equals. To flesh out this objection, we may start with the claim that an entity that has moral status matters morally for their own sake. Some entities, such as a rock, do not have moral status. This means that there must be a reason which explains why the former entity has moral status and the rock does not. There must be some property, or properties, which this entity holds and in virtue of which it has moral status which the rock does not hold (Floris Reference Floris2022: 4). Arneson (Reference Arneson and Steinhoff2015) argues that the most plausible such property is rational agency capacity.Footnote 14 Entities with moral status have the capacity for rational agency. They can ‘identify available courses of action [they] might take, discern reasons for and against the options, weigh and assess the reasons [they] discern, deliberate and make choices, carry out the action chosen, and do all this not simply for a single decision problem at a time but with respect to long-term plans of action and projects [they] might undertake’ (Arneson Reference Arneson and Steinhoff2015: 33–34).

Moral unequals are thus entities that possess rational agency capacity to different degrees.Footnote 15 Assuming this understanding, parents and (small) children are clearly moral unequals (Floris Reference Floris2022). But most people do not believe that parents and (small) children should relate as social equals, i.e. that they should have the same degree of power and de facto authority in the relationship (the same goes for adult humans and animals). Most believe that the parent should have more power and de facto authority than the child, for example to decide when the child is to go to bed and what the child is to eat. Thus, one might argue, broad non-responsibility-sensitive relational egalitarianism implies that parent and child, being moral unequals, should relate as social equals and this is implausible because it means that they should have equal power and de facto authority. To avoid this, one may instead support:

Narrow Non-responsibility-sensitive Relational Egalitarianism: A situation is just only if moral equals relate as moral and social equals and moral unequals relate as moral and social unequals.Footnote 16

According to this view, parent and (small) child, being moral unequals, should not relate as moral and social equals. Thus, it avoids the objection pressed against broad non-responsibility-sensitive relational egalitarianism. But this also means that according to narrow non-responsibility-sensitive relational egalitarianism, equal relations can be unjust. Since it prescribes that moral unequals must relate as social unequals, it is unjust if parent and (small) child, being moral unequals, relate as social equals.

One may find this intuitively objectionable. Is it not a bit too much to say that it is unjust if parent and (small) child relate as social equals? It may not be once we notice that this may actually be what is best for the (small) child. Clearly, a two-year-old does not know what is best for them, at least long-term, because they do not yet have a fully developed self with attached life plans and interests. If parent and two-year-old child were to relate as social equals, it would mean that the child would have as much power and authority as their parent in deciding what to eat, when to go to bed, whether to use the tablet etc. We can easily see that this would be bad for the child; that the child would be a worse chooser than their parent with regard to promotion of the child’s interests. In that sense, it does not look objectionable that the parent and child ought to relate as social unequals, as Narrow Non-responsibility-sensitive Relational Egalitarianism prescribes, since it might actually promote the interests of the child that the parent has more power than them. Or so a defender of narrow non-responsibility-sensitive relational egalitarianism may say.Footnote 17

At this point, one might object that the parent-child example does not in fact show what I intend it to show. One may agree that it is wrong for a parent to conduct their relationship with their child on a footing of equal power and authority (i.e. that they relate as social equals) when this is detrimental to their child’s fundamental interests, regarding which they have fiduciary duties. However, it is not obvious that the wrongness is explicable with reference to relational egalitarian considerations. It seems plausible, instead, that relational equality puts pressure on the parent-child relationship to be made egalitarian, but that this pressure is constrained by the fundamental interests of the child in being treated paternalistically. So perhaps the relationship should simply be as egalitarian as is consistent with promoting the interests of the child. If so, then the parent-child example does not seem to show that equal relations can be unjust on relational grounds, as opposed to being wrong on nonrelational grounds having to do with lack of promotion of the child’s interests (cf. the clarification in relation to the first question in the Introduction).Footnote 18

I have the following responses. First, the fact that the parent and child relating as social unequals may in fact promote the interests of the child is appealed to on behalf of Narrow Non-responsibility-sensitive Relational Egalitarianism to show that it may in fact not be an implausible implication of the view that it implies that parent and child ought to relate as social unequals. But it is not an argument for why parent and child must relate as social unequals on this view. The reason they should relate as social unequals, according to this view, is that they are moral unequals (the view says that moral unequals ought to relate as social unequals). Another way of making this point is to say that even if it happened to not be in the child’s interests to relate as a social inferior to their parent, Narrow Non-responsibility-sensitive Relational Egalitarianism would still say that they should relate as social unequals precisely because they are moral unequals. Of course, one may disagree with this particular verdict. But this would simply speak against the view. It would not show that there was not a relational concern at stake.

Second, perhaps a cleaner case is to consider a relationship between an adult human and an animal, say, a dog.Footnote 19 Many believe that animals, including dogs, have a lower moral status than adult humans (see e.g. Jaworska and Tannenbaum Reference Jaworska and Tannenbaum2014; Kagan Reference Kagan2019).Footnote 20 If this is true, it would be unjust if an adult human and a dog were to relate as social equals according to Narrow Non-responsibility-sensitive Relational Egalitarianism, for example if they had the same degree of power and authority. Since they are moral unequals, they should relate as social unequals. And again, this should be the case, according to this view, irrespective of whether the dog’s interests would be better promoted if they related as social equals instead. One may find this implausible. But, again, this would be a reason to reject the Narrow Non-responsibility-sensitive view (and would not be something that shows that what is at stake is not relational concerns).

So much for the non-responsibility-sensitive conceptions of relational egalitarianism. We have seen that according to broad non-responsibility-sensitive relational egalitarianism, no equal relation can be unjust. According to narrow non-responsibility-sensitive relational egalitarianism, on the other hand, some equal relations are unjust. For instance, it is unjust if moral unequals relate as social equals. Interestingly, this means that even among conceptions of relational egalitarianism that do not take responsibility into account, there is disagreement as to whether equal relations can be unjust.

Before I move on, I would like to address the following worry. Sure, it is a logical possibility that there is a non-responsibility-sensitive conception of relational egalitarianism in which equal relations can be unjust. However, this possibility seems removed from what relational egalitarians have defended and for that reason is not particularly interesting.Footnote 21 I have two responses. First, it is not true that relational egalitarians have not defended a view along these lines. Bengtson (Reference Bidadanure2022) argues, assuming that animals and human adults are not moral equals, that it is unjust if they relate as equals since moral unequals should relate as unequals. So a non-responsibility-sensitive conception of relational egalitarianism does not seem removed from what relational egalitarians have defended, or at least discussed. Second, even if it were true that no relational egalitarian had defended a view along these lines, it may still be valuable to find out what committing to such a view would imply. For one thing, it illustrates the breadth in relational egalitarianism: that relational egalitarianism can mean many different things. For another, it shows that if one wants a relational egalitarian view in which equal relations can be unjust, one does not have to commit to a responsibility-sensitive view.

3. Responsibility-sensitive Conceptions of Relational Egalitarianism

Let us now turn to responsibility-sensitive conceptions of relational egalitarianism. As mentioned earlier, Lippert-Rasmussen (Reference Lippert-Rasmussen2018: 7) presents the following conception:

Luck relational egalitarianism: A situation is just only if no one relates to others as (superiors/) inferiors through no responsibility of their own.

According to this view, unequal relations which are not due to differences in exercises of responsibility are unjust. It is unjust if Man and Woman relate as social unequals in a sexist society since this, let us assume, has nothing to do with them exercising their agency in different ways. It is simply that the norms in this society prescribe that men are socially superior to women.

May some equal relations be unjust according to luck relational egalitarianism? Notice that this view is negative in the sense that it deems it unjust if relations are unequal for reasons other than differential exercises of responsibility. But at the same time, it is silent on whether it is unjust that relations are equal assuming differential exercises of responsibility. It only tells us that relations must not be unequal except for differences in exercise of responsibility. So it does not provide an answer to our question of whether some equal relations are unjust according to relational egalitarianism. Since this is a negative view, let us refer to it as Negative Responsibility-sensitive Relational Egalitarianism (instead of luck relational egalitarianism). We may then distinguish this view from the following view:

Positive Responsibility-sensitive Relational Egalitarianism: A situation is just only if everyone relates to others in accordance with their exercise of responsibility.

This view is a relational egalitarian view in the sense that it assumes a baseline of equality (cf. Olsaretti Reference Olsaretti2002: 396).Footnote 22 If there are not differential exercises of responsibility, relations should be equal. Some have recently argued that we should make relational egalitarianism responsibility-sensitive. Indeed, in a recent paper, Schmidt (Reference Schmidt2022) argues that responsibility practices are a constitutive aspect of flourishing, egalitarian relationships in the first place. And, moreover, that society must be organized in a way that takes this fact into account. He presents the following example:

Money Burner: Petra receives her salary twice a year. Yet upon receiving her salary, Petra burns 90% of it, which leaves her destitute. (Schmidt Reference Schmidt2022: 1376)

He imagines that this takes place in Equalia, ‘a society bent on minimizing relational inequalities’. In this society, ‘institutions are set up such that Petra’s lack of resources will be compensated to the point where she again stands in perfect relational equality with all other citizens’ (Schmidt Reference Schmidt2022: 1376). As Schmidt explains, one of the problems with Equalia’s institutions is that they facilitate costless reneging. ‘Someone engages in costless reneging’, Schmidt (Reference Schmidt2022: 1388) explains, ‘when she acquires obligations to other participants, does not discharge such obligations, bears no significant costs as a result, and it would be appropriate to hold her responsible (in the attributability sense) for acquiring the obligations and for not discharging them’. Because Equalia’s institutions are not responsibility-sensitive, they let Petra ‘get away’ with burning 90% of her salary. In this case, Petra engages in costless reneging against the other citizens in Equalia. To see why this leads to objectionable relational equality, we need to introduce a distinction between the following two forms of relational (in)equality:

Synchronic Relational Egalitarianism: Justice requires that, at any given moment, people relate socially to one another as equals.

Diachronic Relational Egalitarianism: Justice requires that, from the perspective of their lives as a whole, people relate socially to one another as equals. (Lippert-Rasmussen Reference Lippert-Rasmussen2019: 154)

To see the difference between these views, suppose that Xavier exploits Yoel for 30 years after which Yoel exploits Xavier for 30 years (cf. Lippert-Rasmussen Reference Lippert-Rasmussen2019: 155). In this case, Xavier and Yoel relate as equals from the perspective of diachronic relational egalitarianism, but not according to synchronic relational egalitarianism since at no point in time in their lives do they relate as social equals (see also Bidadanure Reference Bidadanure2016).

Equalia’s institutions are set up to always secure synchronic relational equality. If Petra’s burning 90% of her salary leaves her destitute, Equalia’s institutions secure that she is compensated to an extent that she is no longer destitute such that synchronic relational equality is restored (at least to that extent). In this way, Equalia’s institutions enable costless reneging such that there are no consequences for Petra in not taking into account other people’s interests.Footnote 23 Those who engage in costless reneging thus treat other people in society as lesser participants in their cooperative undertaking, thereby creating diachronic relational inequality. As Schmidt (Reference Schmidt2022: 1388) says, ‘more generally, when we separate distributions from responsibility entirely, we might set up social structures that enable costless reneging and thereby diachronic relational inequality’.

We can see how this is unjust according to positive responsibility-sensitive relational egalitarianism. When the system facilitates costless reneging, everyone does not relate to others in accordance with their exercise of responsibility. Given that Equalia compensates Petra, she relates, in the synchronic sense, as a social equal to the other citizens of Equalia, according to Schmidt: that is what the institutions in Equalia secure. But they have exercised their responsibility quite differently: Petra has irresponsibly burned 90% of her income while they have not. According to positive responsibility-sensitive relational egalitarianism, the relationships should reflect this such that Petra ought to relate as an inferior to the other citizens – justice provides a reason not to compensate her.Footnote 24 That is, the equal relations between Petra and the other citizens are unjust.

Schmidt presents another case which is relevant for our purposes. Consider:

Carlton: Bella works as a bouncer at a night club. She is instructed to admit at most a few Black persons per night. Bella herself is Black and working class. One night a group of wealthy private school boys arrive. Among them is Carlton, a Black student with a rich Belair background. Bella lets in all the rich white boys but sends Carlton away. (Schmidt Reference Schmidt2022: 1378)

Schmidt uses this example to show how the social context matters to how people relate to each other. In this case, the discrimination Carlton faces results in a relational inequality between him and his white friends. As Schmidt (Reference Schmidt2022: 1389) concludes, ‘[Carlton shows that] relational inequality can be generated between two groups (or between individuals) when a third party treats them in a way that expresses unequal status’. But if objectionable relational inequality can be generated between two groups, or individuals, when a third party treats them in a way that expresses unequal status, we might also think that objectionable relational equality can be generated between two groups, or individuals, when a third party treats them in a way that expresses equal status. Money Burner might be an instance of this. When Equalia’s institutions compensate Petra to secure synchronic equality between Petra and other citizens, their treatment may be said to express equal status in the synchronic sense and be objectionable for this reason (even if it might also express unequal status in the diachronic sense), especially if intentions are part of what determines what an act expresses (Scanlon Reference Scanlon2008: 53; Lippert-Rasmussen Reference Lippert-Rasmussen2018: 77). The treatment expresses that Petra and other citizens relate as synchronic equals, but it should not since they should not relate as synchronic equals given their differential exercise of responsibility – at least according to positive responsibility-sensitive relational egalitarianism. Some might disagree with what this particular example expresses. That is fine with me since it does not challenge the general point in this paragraph: if objectionable relational inequality can be generated between two groups, or individuals, when a third party treats them in a way that expresses unequal status, objectionable relational equality can be generated between two groups, or individuals, when a third party treats them in a way that expresses equal status. Thus, we have now seen two ways in which equal relations may be unjust according to positive responsibility-sensitive relational egalitarianism.

Stemplowska (Reference Stemplowska, Knight and Stemplowska2011) has also argued that relational egalitarianism should be responsibility-sensitive. She argues that ‘we should recognize that being owed respect as a social equal is conditional upon respecting others as one’s moral equals. That is, only those who respect equality of moral status should themselves be recognized as being owed respect as social equals’ (Stemplowska Reference Stemplowska, Knight and Stemplowska2011: 131).Footnote 25 Suppose that Criminal treats Victim in a wrongful manner, for example by beating them up. In doing so, Criminal fails to respect Victim as their moral equal, i.e. they fail to treat Victim’s interests as fundamentally of equal importance to their own. But if Stemplowska is right, this means that Criminal should not ‘be recognized as being owed respect as social equals’ (or at least that Criminal is not owed such recognition). Indeed, as Stemplowska (Reference Stemplowska, Knight and Stemplowska2011: 133) says, ‘the proponents of the ideal of equal social respect [relational egalitarianism] would not want to (and, in fact, do not)Footnote 26 argue that even the perpetrators of hideous crimes must be respected as social equals by others’. In this way, how people should relate to each other in terms of social standing depends on how they have exercised their responsibility in relation to treating others as moral (un)equals. This is in line with, although narrower than, positive responsibility-sensitive relational egalitarianism: justice requires that Criminal and Victim relate as social unequals since Criminal has failed to respect Victim as their moral equal.

At this point, one might object in the following way. When I laid out what it takes to relate as moral and social equals in section 2, I seemed to think of equal relations in terms of some fixed formula, for example equal power, such that any power inequality makes a relationship inegalitarian. However, it is not clear that relational egalitarians must be committed to the view that inequalities of power necessarily make a relationship inegalitarian. A relational egalitarian may hold, for instance, that to relate to Criminal as a moral equal is to impose appropriate punishment on them, and such punishment may be to grant Criminal less power, for example in the form of (temporary) disenfranchisement. On this view, imposing the power inequality is part and parcel of relating to the offender as an equal. More generally, relational egalitarians endorse various ‘tempering factors’ (Kolodny Reference Kolodny2023: 98) that render power inequalities morally unproblematic, or at least less problematic. This seems to be a different view of what an egalitarian relationship is. Assuming this view, it is not clear how the Criminal-Victim example provides an example of an unjust equal relation.Footnote 27

I have the following responses. First, I do not mean to deny that relational egalitarians endorse various tempering factors. Indeed, I mention some of them in the next section when presenting Kolodny’s view of why the political domain is particularly important for how people relate to each other (see also Kolodny Reference Kolodny2023: 97–101, 125–126). Second, as I have emphasized throughout the paper, relational egalitarianism is not merely one view. There are many different conceptions of relational egalitarianism. And my aim in this paper has not been to defend any particular conception. My aim has been to investigate whether equal relations can be unjust on different conceptions of relational egalitarianism. So I agree that a relational egalitarian could support the view laid out in the objection, i.e. that to relate to Criminal as a moral equal is to hold them accountable and thus to impose appropriate punishment on them. The relevant question for our purposes is: can an equal relation be unjust on this view? One way to argue for an affirmative answer is as follows. Here, the distinction between relating as moral equals and relating as social equals, which I laid out in section 2, becomes important. If we assume that relating to Criminal as a moral equal is to hold them accountable and thus to impose appropriate punishment on them, then this may at the same time affect how Criminal relates to others as social equals. As we will see in the next section, equal political power is, according to Kolodny and other relational egalitarians, a particularly important constituent part of relating as social equals. In other words, if X and Y have unequal political power, X and Y relate as social unequals. Now, if the appropriate punishment in terms of relating to Criminal as a moral equal is (temporary) disenfranchisement, then holding Criminal responsible entails that Criminal relates to others – those with more political power – as a social unequal. Ensuring equal moral standing in this case requires unequal social standing. The view requires that we relate to Criminal as a moral equal and a social unequal. Suppose now that we failed to hold Criminal responsible. In that case, Criminal would not have less political power than others and would therefore, all else equal, relate to others as a social equal. In that case, we would not realize what the view required, namely that we relate to Criminal as a moral equal (by holding them responsible for what they did) and a social unequal (by granting them less political power than others). In that case, both the unequal moral relation and the equal social relation would be unjust. If so, that would be an example of how there could be an unjust equal relation on this view.

Third, even if we assume that the suggestion in the previous paragraph is false – indeed, even if we assume that on the view in question, no equal relations can be unjust – this would not threaten what I have been arguing in this paper. It would, in that case, simply point to a responsibility-sensitive conception of relational egalitarianism in which equal relations could not be unjust (the view would therefore be different from Stemplowska’s view laid out above). And this would be in line with my argument that whether equal relations can be unjust cuts across the distinction between responsibility-sensitive and non-responsibility-sensitive conceptions of relational egalitarianism.

To sum up this section, we have seen that responsibility-sensitive conceptions of relational egalitarianism give different answers to whether equal relations can be unjust. Negative responsibility-sensitive relational egalitarianism is simply silent on this question: it only tells us that it is unjust if relations are unequal for reasons other than differential exercises of responsibility. According to positive responsibility-sensitive relational egalitarianism, equal relations can be unjust. In total, we have investigated four different conceptions of relational egalitarianism, two which are responsibility-sensitive and two which are not. Surprisingly, we have seen that whether equal relations can be unjust cuts across the distinction between responsibility-sensitive and non-responsibility-sensitive conceptions of relational egalitarianism.

4. Unjust Equal Relations: Further Implications

In this section, I will continue with the two conceptions of relational egalitarianism according to which equal relations can be unjust. I want to do so to explore the further implications of committing to such a view. In that sense, the investigation should hopefully be useful in answering the question of whether we should prefer a conception of relational egalitarianism according to which equal relations can be unjust, or one in which they cannot. I cannot hope to fully settle this question in this paper, but I will point to some of the implications that follow if one supports a relational egalitarian view according to which equal relations can be unjust.

According to prominent relational egalitarians, equal political power is a particularly important constituent part of relating as equals. Kolodny (Reference Kolodny2014; see also Anderson Reference Anderson1999; Viehoff Reference Viehoff2014; Peña-Rangel Reference Peña-Rangel2022) makes this argument. He explains that equal political power is a particularly important constituent because political decisions (i) cannot usually be escaped at will; (ii) have final de facto authority; and (iii) involve force. (i) is important because ability to escape a decision at will makes a difference to what would otherwise be an unequal relation. Suppose Slave can exit their slave contract. If so, the relation between Master and Slave is not unequal in the way it would be if the slave could not escape the contract at will. Indeed, ‘the freer one is to exit what would otherwise be a relation of social inferiority, the less it seems a relation of social inferiority in the first place’ (Kolodny Reference Kolodny2014: 305). And, according to Kolodny, the thing with political decisions is that one cannot usually escape them at will (in the same way that one can escape non-political decisions).

With regard to (ii),

suppose that lord and servant set terms at the start of each year, somehow with genuinely equal influence, over how the lord is to boss the servant around … In such a case, the fact that they have equal influence over decisions higher up, as it were, the chain of command, which set the terms for how other, lower-order decisions are to be made, plays a role in avoiding, or moderating, the social inferiority that unequal influence over those decisions would otherwise entail. (Kolodny Reference Kolodny2014: 305)

Equality when it comes to higher-order decisions eliminates, or at least moderates, the inequality which exists between Lord and Servant when it comes to lower-order decisions. Political decisions are important for relational equality because they are the highest-order decisions, as it were. They have final de facto authority. There are two implications we can draw from this. First, if there is inequality in influence over political decisions, this inequality cannot be moderated by equality in influence at a higher-order level (since there is no higher-order level). Second, if there is equality of influence with regard to higher-order decisions, this moderates the threat to relational equality posed by unequal influence over lower-order decisions. As Kolodny (Reference Kolodny2014: 306) says, ‘the threat to social equality that hierarchy would otherwise pose, one might say, is moderated by the fact that whatever hierarchy there may be is ultimately regulated or authorized from a standpoint of equality’.

With regard to (iii) – that political decisions involve force – Kolodny (Reference Kolodny2014: 307) notes that force is particularly important to how people relate ‘because, as a contingent matter, the power to use force is the ‘final’ power … [in the sense that it is] the power that usually determines the distribution of other powers’. That Smart is smarter than Brute is of no use to Smart if Brute can subject them to force: ‘One cannot reliably have superior powers of other kinds over others where they have superior powers to subject one to force’ (Kolodny Reference Kolodny2014: 307). This is to say that symmetry in the capacity to use force is important for relational equality. And political decisions characteristically involve (the threat of) force.

Let us assume Kolodny is right that, for these three reasons, equal political power is a particularly important constituent part of relating as equals.Footnote 28 , Footnote 29 If so, deviating from equal political power must be a particularly important constituent part of relating as unequals. If Victim has more political power than Criminal, that inequality in political power is a particularly important constituent part of their unequal social relation. So this shows that if we want to turn an unjust equal relation into an unequal relation, the most effective way of doing so may be to grant less political power to the one who ought to stand as a social inferior, in casu Criminal. I am not saying that this is necessarily the only way to do so. But note that if Kolodny is right, any way of trying to make the equal relation unequal by intervening in the non-political domain would still leave an important equality intact: the equality in the higher-order domain that is constituted by equal political power. To avoid this, we would have to intervene in the political domain. This shows, interestingly, that, according to relational egalitarian views in which equal relations can be unjust, sometimes we have a pro tanto reason to grant those who should relate as unequals unequal political power.

One may object to this argument in the following way. Suppose we did grant Criminal less political power than Victim. Would that not constitute unjust unequal relations between Criminal and other people in society (who would have more political power than Criminal)? I have three responses to this objection. First, note that the argument points to a pro tanto reason to grant Criminal less political power than Victim. We have a pro tanto reason to grant Criminal less political power than Victim because they ought to relate as social unequals. But insofar as this would also lead to unequal relations between Criminal and other people in society, it may be that, all things considered, it would be better not to grant Criminal less political power than Victim. But this does not mean that the pro tanto reason goes away. It simply means that we have to weigh that reason against other reasons when making an all things considered judgement of how to distribute political power.

Second, we could imagine situations in which it would not constitute unjust unequal relations to grant Criminal less political power than Victim, for example if half of the people in society were criminals and the other half were victims. In this case, we might have both a pro tanto reason and an all things considered reason to grant Criminal (indeed all the criminals) less political power than Victim (indeed all the victims).

Third, perhaps the unequal relations between Criminal and other people in society that may be constituted by giving Criminal less political power are not objectionable. After all, Criminal has acted against the norms of relational equality in the community by treating Victim as their moral inferior. But if they have acted against the norms of relational equality, they might thereby have forfeited their relational egalitarian claims of standing as a social equal to others as well (at least for a while).Footnote 30 If so, there may be other reasons for why Criminal should not relate in an unequal manner to other citizens, but it would not be unjust that they did so (cf. Stemplowska Reference Stemplowska, Knight and Stemplowska2011: 133). The upshot is that assuming a conception of relational egalitarianism in which equal relations can be unjust, we may sometimes, for reasons of justice, have to deviate from a system of ‘one person, one vote.’

Another implication of accounts in which equal relations may be unjust is the following: there may be situations in which relational egalitarian justice requires what is bad for individuals.Footnote 31 Sometimes unequal relations may be bad for the individuals involved, for example because they would get too caught up in the inequality or because it would lead to inappropriate thoughts of superiority – thoughts including too much superiority, as it were – for the one standing as a superior. In some of these cases, however, conceptions of relational egalitarianism in which equal relations may be unjust may still imply that an equal relation would be unjust. Note, first, that this is not a special characteristic of conceptions of relational egalitarianism according to which equal relations may be unjust. It is a consequence of non-consequentialist theories in general – as opposed to consequentialist theories – that they entail that justice may not always require what will have the best (personal) consequences. Second, conceptions of relational egalitarianism according to which equal relations cannot be unjust may have a similar implication. Such conceptions may in some situations imply that justice requires equal relations even if unequal relations would be better for the individuals involved. Think for instance of the parent-child example mentioned earlier. In that case, an unequal relationship may clearly be beneficial for the child. Moreover, as Lippert-Rasmussen (Reference Lippert-Rasmussen2018: 10) explains, Burke famously argued that

hierarchy, instead of thoroughly egalitarian social relations, gives those who end up at the lower end of the hierarchy the chance of virtuous modesty and deference which might be better for them, social relations-wise, than some bland form of equality, which homogenizes and vulgarizes everything.

We must not forget that just as equal relations can sometimes be beneficial, even if unjust, unequal relations can also sometimes be beneficial, even if unjust. In this sense, conceptions of relational egalitarianism in which equal relations can be unjust are not different from those in which they cannot.

A third implication of conceptions of relational egalitarianism in which equal relations can be unjust is that they in one sense become similar to some conceptions of luck egalitarianism, to wit, in the sense that equality may be unjust. With regard to relational egalitarianism, in the sense that equal relations may be unjust. With regard to luck egalitarianism, in the sense that equal distributions may be unjust. Let me unfold this. Distributive theories of justice claim that justice has to do with distributions. According to the most prominent distributive theory of justice, luck egalitarianism, individuals’ distributive positions should reflect only their relative exercise of responsibility (Lippert-Rasmussen Reference Lippert-Rasmussen2015). Albertsen and Midtgaard (Reference Albertsen and Midtgaard2014) convincingly argue that luck-generated equalities and inequalities should be treated similarly: that luck egalitarianism in this sense is symmetric.Footnote 32 Just as it is unjust that Adam is worse off, distributions-wise, than Bertram through brute luck, it is unjust that Carr is as well off as Derek through brute luck. They introduce the following case to illustrate their view:

Prudent and Lazy: Prudent and Lazy are two survivors on a desert … island. While Lazy lies on the beach, Prudent goes fishing and returns with a fish that she then proceeds to grill and enjoy on her own. Their respective levels of welfare are now, let us say, 10 for Lazy (hungry but rested), and 20 for Prudent. LE [luck egalitarianism] and desert agree that there is nothing unjust in this unequal state of affairs … Imagine now that a nice big fish washes up alongside Lazy, who, recall, is simply lying there. This turn of events generates a new distribution … where now both Lazy and Prudent have 20 units of welfare. (Albertsen and Midtgaard Reference Albertsen and Midtgaard2014: 338; they borrow the case from Segall Reference Segall2010: 17)

They argue that the resulting equality between Prudent and Lazy is unjust since ‘the effects of differential brute luck should consistently be neutralized’ (Albertsen and Midtgaard Reference Albertsen and Midtgaard2014: 338). Their main argument for this symmetrical view of luck egalitarianism is that it would be unfair not to neutralize the effects of brute luck in cases of equal distributions. When people, assuming a background of equal opportunities, exercise their responsibility to different degrees, they are not in a position in which they can justifiably demand that equalizing measures be set up (Albertsen and Midtgaard Reference Albertsen and Midtgaard2014: 337). As they explain, ‘the profound unfairness of equality in the presence of differential exercises of responsibility is that it amounts to asking some to bear the costs of others’ voluntary choices … it countenances exploitative cost displacement’ (Albertsen and Midtgaard Reference Albertsen and Midtgaard2014: 340). Note that there is a striking similarity between this argument and the relational egalitarian argument, put forward by Schmidt (Reference Schmidt2022), discussed earlier, to wit, the problem of costless reneging. Just as instances of costless reneging may lead to unjust equal relations, instances of exploitative cost displacement may lead to unjust equal distributions. In this sense, both relational egalitarianism and luck egalitarianism, and for strikingly similar reasons, entail that equality may be unjust.

This result is significant in itself. But it is also significant since it points to an interesting similarity between relational egalitarians and luck egalitarians. According to some relational egalitarians, relational egalitarianism and luck egalitarianism are competitors – indeed, are incompatible (of course, this could still be true even if there are important structural similarities between luck egalitarianism and relational egalitarianism; settling whether this is so goes beyond the scope of this paper). Take for instance the following remarks from Anderson, arguably the most prominent relational egalitarian:

Democratic equality [relational egalitarianism] is … a relational theory of equality: it views equality as a social relationship. Equality of fortune [luck egalitarianism] is a distributive theory of equality: it conceives of equality as a pattern of distribution. Thus, equality of fortune regards two people as equal as long as they enjoy equal amounts of some distributable good – income, resources, opportunities for welfare and so forth. Social relations are largely seen as instrumental to generating such patterns of distribution. By contrast, democratic equality regards two people as equal when each accepts the obligation to justify their actions by principles acceptable to the other, and in which they take mutual consultation, reciprocation and recognition for granted. Certain patterns in the distribution of goods may be instrumental to securing such relationships, follow from them, or even be constitutive of them. But democratic egalitarians are fundamentally concerned with the relationships within which goods are distributed, not only with the distribution of goods themselves. (Anderson Reference Anderson1999: 313–314; see also Anderson Reference Anderson2010b; Scheffler Reference Scheffler, Fourie, Schuppert and Walliman-Helmer2015: 21–22)

As she ends by saying, there is disagreement at the fundamental level between luck and relational egalitarians: according to the former, distributions are fundamental; according to the latter, relations are fundamental.

Others have pushed back on Anderson’s argument that luck egalitarianism and relational egalitarianism are incompatible in this sense. They have argued for a pluralist conception of justice which includes both distributive and relational concerns (see e.g. Lippert-Rasmussen Reference Lippert-Rasmussen2018; Moles and Parr Reference Moles and Parr2019; Mulkeen Reference Mulkeen2020). The argument presented here – that both relational egalitarianism and luck egalitarianism, and for strikingly similar reasons, entail that equality may be unjust – may (not: necessarily do) provide further support for the argument that luck and relational egalitarianism, at least on some conceptions thereof, are not competitors nor incompatible.

5. Conclusion

In this paper, I have tackled the question of whether equal relations can be unjust according to relational egalitarianism – a theory of justice according to which justice requires equal relations. Relational egalitarianism is not a single theory. It is a large family of theories that differ along many different dimensions. I distinguished between two non-responsibility-sensitive conceptions of relational egalitarianism (a narrow and a broad one) and two responsibility-sensitive conceptions of relational egalitarianism (a negative and a positive one). I argued that whether equal relations can be unjust surprisingly cuts across the distinction between responsibility-sensitive and non-responsibility-sensitive conceptions of relational egalitarianism. In that sense, one can support a non-responsibility-sensitive conception of relational egalitarianism even if one does not want equality across the board. In relation to the second question I posed in the Introduction – if equal relations can be unjust, how does this, implications-wise, affect relational egalitarianism as a theory of justice? – I have pointed to three implications: (1) that we sometimes have reason to grant some people less political power than others; (2) that relational egalitarian justice sometimes requires what is bad for individuals; and (3) that it points to an interesting similarity between luck egalitarianism and relational egalitarianism.

Acknowledgements

For helpful written comments on previous versions of this paper, I thank Søren Flinch Midtgaard, Andreas T. Schmidt and two anonymous reviewers for Economics and Philosophy. For funding, I am grateful to the Danish National Research Foundation (DNRF144) and the Independent Research Fund Denmark (1027-00002B).

Andreas Bengtson is a Postdoctoral Researcher at the Centre for the Experimental-Philosophical Study of Discrimination at Department of Political Science, Aarhus University. He has published on issues such as affirmative action, democratic theory, discrimination, paternalism and relational equality. His work has appeared in journals such as American Journal of Political Science, British Journal of Political Science, Ergo, Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, Journal of Moral Philosophy, Politics, Philosophy & Economics and Journal of Political Philosophy. URL: www.andreasbengtson.com

Footnotes

2 The parallel question on distributive views of justice (to which I return later) would be: can equal distributions never be unjust?

3 For arguments that relational egalitarianism should be responsibility-sensitive, see e.g. Stemplowska (Reference Stemplowska, Knight and Stemplowska2011) and Schmidt (Reference Schmidt2022). I return to these arguments in section 3.

4 I thank an anonymous reviewer for suggesting that I make this clarification.

5 Later in this section, I return to the view that equal relations are impersonally valuable.

6 As a reviewer notes, this might not single out responsibility-insensitive views since it might be that what relating as moral equals requires is that we give proper weight to others’ exercise of their responsibilities. I will later discuss a view on which relating to another as a moral equal requires giving proper weight to their exercise of responsibility (see section 4). Non-responsibility-sensitive Relational Egalitarianism does not take exercises of responsibility into account in this way. Compare the discussion in relation to distributive views of whether people should have equal amounts of well-being or whether they should have equally good opportunities for well-being (Lippert-Rasmussen Reference Lippert-Rasmussen2018: 6). Non-responsibility-sensitive Moral Relational Egalitarianism is of the former type.

7 To be clear, Sexist takes Women’s agency to be less important in the sense that there is less reason to respect it (than if she had been a man).

8 With this being said, moral and social standing are clearly related, for example failing to relate as moral equals, say, because of sexism, arguably also entails that Sexist and Woman fail to relate as social equals.

9 There are other understandings of social standing, for example one proposed by van Wietmarschen (Reference van Wietmarschen2022). But Kolodny’s account plays a prominent role among relational egalitarians. And, in any case, the differences between Kolodny’s account and other proposed accounts make no crucial differences to the argument I will make in this paper. With suitable modifications, we can make similar arguments assuming, say, van Wietmarschen’s view that ‘a social position A is ‘higher than’ or ‘above’ social position B if and only if, for the participants in the relevant social network, when they display the norm-required complexes of attitude and behaviour they thereby and to that extent value the occupants of A more than the occupants of B’ (van Wietmarschen Reference van Wietmarschen2022: 925).

10 To this component, and the de facto authority component, he adds a ‘while’ clause. For A to have a superior social standing to A, not only must A have more power and/or de facto authority. They must have those ‘while not being resolutely disposed to refrain from exercising that greater power as something to which those others are entitled’ (Kolodny Reference Kolodny2014: 296).

11 Bengtson and Lippert-Rasmussen (Reference Bengtson and Lippert-Rasmussen2023) explore this view.

12 Actually, O’Neill’s argument is ambiguous. It is not clear whether egalitarian relationships are impersonally valuable because they are (i) egalitarian (such that it is the fact that they are egalitarian that brings the value), or (ii) accurate (such that there is value in moral equals relating as equals, slight moral unequals relating as slight unequals, etc.). If the former, egalitarian relationships between moral unequals would be impersonally valuable. If the latter, egalitarian relationships between moral unequals would not be impersonally valuable qua lacking accuracy. As a reviewer notes, it seems that Viehoff’s remark mentioned above – ‘If we are all moral equals, matter equally, etc., then social status hierarchy is objectionable because it treats us as if we were not’ (Viehoff Reference Viehoff, Sobel, Vallentyne and Wall2019: 18) – may support the accuracy interpretation. See also Bengtson and Lippert-Rasmussen (Reference Bengtson and Lippert-Rasmussen2023: 388).

13 I discuss a relationship between an adult human and an animal later in this section.

14 But this is not to suggest that Arneson supports this rational agency capacity account. He only points out that it seems to be the most plausible account. But he further argues that this account runs into significant problems (Arneson Reference Arneson and Steinhoff2015: 36).

15 Philosophical discussions of basic moral equality have shown how difficult it is to identify the properties in virtue of which human beings are moral equals. As Arneson (Reference Arneson and Steinhoff2015: 42) sums up this problem: ‘Either the proposed basis [the property, or properties, proposed to ground equal moral status] will turn out to vary by degree, and variations above the claimed threshold that establishes equality will give rise to inequality of moral considerability, or the proposed basis will turn out to be one that applies in an all-or-nothing fashion, and then it will turn out that the basis proposed as justifying equal moral considerability is too flimsy or insubstantial to do this justifying work’ (see also Singer Reference Singer1990, Reference Singer2011; Arneson Reference Arneson and Jamieson1999; Carter Reference Carter2011; Husi Reference Husi2017; Parr and Slavny Reference Parr and Slavny2019).

16 There may also be the view that social relations between moral unequals are neither good nor bad. I set aside this view.

17 Could one not imagine situations in which people differ in rational agency capacity but to a much lesser extent than parent and small child such that it would not be unjust for them, even though they are moral unequals, to relate as social equals? Perhaps, but that is fully compatible with my argument here, namely that some equal relations will be unjust according to Narrow Non-responsibility-sensitive Relational Egalitarianism. Also, why not say instead that they should relate as unequals to the extent that they are unequals, instead of saying that they should then relate as equals?

18 I thank an anonymous reviewer for raising this objection.

19 I thank an anonymous reviewer for this suggestion.

20 But some deny this, see e.g. DeGrazia (Reference DeGrazia1996) and Singer (Reference Singer2009).

21 I thank an anonymous reviewer for suggesting that I address this worry.

22 We could imagine a different responsibility-sensitive view in which the baseline is hierarchy but where deviations from hierarchy are justified by differential exercises of responsibility. This would be an inegalitarian view. I therefore set it aside.

23 That this leads to relational inequality is clear from Scheffler’s egalitarian deliberative constraint: ‘If you and I have an egalitarian relationship, then I have a standing disposition to treat your strong interests as playing just as significant a role as mine in constraining our decisions and influencing what we will do. And you have a reciprocal disposition with regard to my interests. In addition, both of us normally act on these dispositions. This means that each of our equally important interests constrains our joint decisions to the same extent’ (Scheffler Reference Scheffler, Fourie, Schuppert and Walliman-Helmer2015: 25; cf. Viehoff Reference Viehoff2014: 353).

24 What sort of unequal relations are plausible candidates here? The most obvious one may be the one (hinted at in the text) that may result from not compensating Petra for now being poor. As some relational egalitarians have argued, relational inequality may result from significant differences in wealth (e.g. Schemmel Reference Schemmel2011). That Petra relates as an unequal to others in this sense (at least for a while) may be required. Another candidate may be the following. As mentioned in footnote 23, equal relations require, according to Scheffler, that the parties satisfy the egalitarian deliberative constraint: that they treat each other’s interests as equally important. Thus, if Petra’s interests are treated (at least for a while) as less important than the others’ interests, she will relate to the others as an inferior. That would be another option. I also present a third suggestion later in this section (when discussing a case with Criminal and Victim). I thank an anonymous reviewer for encouraging me to provide some examples here.

25 This in itself does not speak to how moral equals must relate in terms of moral standing. If Stemplowska thinks they must relate as moral equals (and some of her remarks suggest so (Stemplowska Reference Stemplowska, Knight and Stemplowska2011: 130), her view may be compatible with Non-responsibility-sensitive Moral Relational Egalitarianism.

26 She adds this parenthesis as she also provides textual evidence that proponents of relational egalitarianism – Anderson and Scheffler – appeal to intuitions that support social standing being conditional in this way (Stemplowska Reference Stemplowska, Knight and Stemplowska2011: 132).

27 I thank an anonymous reviewer for raising this objection.

28 One may question whether these three factors show that political equality is a constituent of relating as equals. I can remain agnostic on this question. All I need is that the conditions show that the political domain is more important than the non-political domain for how people relate to each other. I thank an anonymous reviewer for raising this issue.

29 For a dissenting view, see Bengtson (2020).

30 The parenthesis may be important. Perhaps the relational egalitarian reason is only strong enough to justify Criminal standing as a social inferior for a while, after which they should again stand as a social equal to others (cf. Stemplowska Reference Stemplowska, Knight and Stemplowska2011: 132). This is also relevant for my argument about unequal political power. It may be that it only justifies granting Criminal less political power for a while, after which they should have as much political power as others.

31 Cf. Anderson’s (Reference Anderson2010b: 27) remarks that Salieri’s ‘complaint [against Mozart’s superior natural musical talent] fails the first constraint on a claim of injustice, that there must be an injury to someone’s interests’.

32 For a dissenting view – according to which luck-generated equalities in distributions are not unjust – see Segall (Reference Segall2010, Reference Segall2012).

References

Albertsen, A. and Midtgaard, S.F. 2014. Unjust equalities. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 17, 335346.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderson, E. 1999. What is the point of equality? Ethics 109, 287337.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderson, E. 2010a. The Imperative of Integration. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderson, E. 2010b. The fundamental disagreement between luck egalitarians and relational egalitarians. Canadian Journal of Philosophy Suppl. Vol. 40, 123.Google Scholar
Arneson, R.J. 1999. What, if anything, renders all humans morally equal? In Peter Singe and His Critics, ed. Jamieson, D., 103128. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Arneson, R.J. 2015. Basic equality: neither acceptable nor rejectable. In Do All Persons Have Equal Moral Worth? On ‘Basic Equality’ and Equal Respect and Concern, ed. Steinhoff, U., 3052. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bengtson A. 2020. Differential voting weights and relational egalitarianism. Political Studies 68, 10541070.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bengtson A. 2022. Animals and relational egalitarianism(s). Journal of Applied Philosophy 40, 7994.Google Scholar
Bengtson, A. and Lippert-Rasmussen, K. 2023. Relational egalitarianism and moral unequals. Journal of Political Philosophy 31, 387410.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bidadanure, J. 2016. Making sense of age-group justice: a time for relational equality? Politics, Philosophy & Economics 15, 234260.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bidadanure, J.U. 2021. Justice Across Ages: Treating Young and Old as Equals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carter, I. 2011. Respect and the basis of equality. Ethics 121, 538571.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
DeGrazia, D. 1996. Taking Animals Seriously. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Floris, G. 2022. Are adults and children one another’s moral equals? Journal of Ethics First View.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fourie, C. 2012. What is social equality? An analysis of status equality as a strongly egalitarian ideal. Res Publica 18, 107126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fourie, C., Schuppert, F. and Walliman-Helmner, I., ed. 2015. Social Equality: On What It Means to be Equals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hojlund, A.S.G. 2022. What should relational egalitarians believe? Politics, Philosophy & Economics 21, 5574.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Husi, S. 2017. Why we (almost certainly) are not moral equals. Journal of Ethics 21, 375401.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jaworska, A. and Tannenbaum, J. 2014. Person-rearing relationships as a key to higher moral status. Ethics 124, 242271.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kagan, S. 2019. How to Count Animals, More or Less. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kolodny, N. 2014. Rule over none II: social equality and the justification of democracy. Philosophy & Public Affairs 42, 287336.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kolodny, N. 2023. The Pecking Order: Social Hierarchy as a Philosophical Problem. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Lippert-Rasmussen, K. 2015. Luck Egalitarianism. London: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
Lippert-Rasmussen, K. 2018. Relational Egalitarianism: Living as Equals. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lippert-Rasmussen, K. 2019. Is it unjust that elderly people suffer from poorer health than young people? Distributive and relational egalitarianism on age-based health inequalities. Politics, Philosophy & Economics 18, 145164.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lippert-Rasmussen, K. 2022. Vote markets, democracy and relational egalitarianism. Economics & Philosophy Online First.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McTernan, E. 2018. Microaggressions, equality, and social practices. Journal of Political Philosophy 26, 261281.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miklosi, Z. 2018. Varieties of relational egalitarianism. In Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy Volume 4, ed. Sobel, D., Vallentyne, P. and Wall, S., 110136. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Miller, D. 1998. Equality and justice. In Ideals of Equality, ed. Mason, A., 2136. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Moles, A. and Parr, T. 2019. Distributions and relations: a hybrid account. Political Studies 67, 132148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mulkeen, N. 2020. Exploitation: bridging social and distributive egalitarianism. Political Studies 68, 954972.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nath, R. 2020. Relational egalitarianism. Philosophy Compass 15, e12686.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O’Neill, M. 2008. What should egalitarians believe? Philosophy & Public Affairs 36, 119156.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Olsaretti, S. 2002. Unmasking equality? Kagan on equality and desert. Utilitas 14, 387400.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parr, T. and Slavny, A. 2019. Rescuing basic equality. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 100, 837857.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peña-Rangel, D. 2022. Political equality, plural voting, and the leveling down objection. Politics, Philosophy & Economics First View.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Satz, D. 2010. Why Some Things Should Not Be For Sale: The Moral Limits of Markets. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scanlon, TM. 2008. Moral Dimensions: Permissibility, Meaning, Blame. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scheffler, S. 2003. What is egalitarianism? Philosophy & Public Affairs 31, 539.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scheffler, S. 2005. Choice, circumstance and the value of equality. Politics, Philosophy and Economics 4, 528.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scheffler, S. 2015. The practice of equality. In Social Equality: On What It Means to be Equals, ed. Fourie, C., Schuppert, F. and Walliman-Helmer, I., 2144. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Schemmel, C. 2011. Why relational egalitarians should care about distributions. Social Theory and Practice 37, 365390.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schemmel, C. 2012. Distributive and relational equality. Politics, Philosophy & Economics 11, 123148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schemmel, C. 2021. Justice and Egalitarian Relations. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schmidt, A.T. 2022. From relational equality to personal responsibility. Philosophical Studies 179, 13731399.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Segall, S. 2010. Health, Luck, and Justice. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Segall, S. 2012. Why egalitarians should not care about equality. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 15, 507519.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Singer, P. 1990. Animal Liberation, 2nd edition. New York, NY: Random House.Google Scholar
Singer, P. 2009. Animal Liberation , updated edition. New York, NY: Harper Collins.Google Scholar
Singer, P. 2011. Practical Ethics, 3rd edition. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stemplowska, Z. 2011. Reconciling two egalitarian visions. In Responsibility and Distributive Justice, ed. Knight, C. and Stemplowska, Z., 115135. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tomlin, P. 2014. What is the point of egalitarian social relationships? In Distributive Justice and Access to Advantage: G. A. Cohen’s Egalitarianism, ed. A. Kaufman, 151179. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Wietmarschen, H. 2022. What is social hierarchy? Noûs 56, 920939.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Viehoff, D. 2014. Democratic equality and political authority. Philosophy & Public Affairs 42, 337375.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Viehoff, D. 2019. Power and equality. In Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy Vol. 5, ed. Sobel, D., Vallentyne, P. and Wall, S., 138. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Voigt, K. 2018. Relational equality and the expressive dimension of state action. Social Theory and Practice 44, 437467.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, J.L. 2019. Democratic Equality. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Wolff, J. 1998. Fairness, respect and the egalitarian ethos. Philosophy & Public Affairs 27, 97122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Young, I.M. 1990. Justice and the Politics of Difference. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar